Berkeley's Treatise and Dialogues As It Is

  1. Philosophy Forum
  2. » Metaphysics
  3. » Berkeley's Treatise and Dialogues As It Is

Get Email Updates Email this Topic Print this Page

Reply Wed 24 Mar, 2010 03:03 am
Extrain;142899 wrote:
How so? I am ready to discuss this point by point.
I presume you have copies of the Treatise and Dialogs in hand (or folder).

I presume you have copies of the Treatise and Dialogs in hand (or folder).

Let's look at the Dialogs first.
Show me where did Berkeley repeat the phrase Esse est percipi in the Dialog.
If this is his central theme, surely he should have repeated it in the Dialogs.

I have numbered the Dialogs and there are 843 conversational paras.
(have not checked whether i have misnumbered, but i don't think this is critical).

Let's take the first 20 paras.
In para 11, Berkeley stated,
That there is no such thing as what PHILOSOPHERS CALL MATERIAL SUBSTANCE.
How would you interpret Berkeley's view of what is material substance as philosophers would called it.
In para 12, Hylas mention the term "matter".
What is Hylas definition of matter?
In para 13, Because Hylas believe in the existence of matter, Berkeley will set out to prove that Hylas is a greater sceptic than he is.
You can refer to other paras to answer the above.
I think we should reconcile (either agree or disagree) the above before we proceeed further.


THE FIRST DIALOGUE

1 PHILONOUS (Berkeley). Good morrow, Hylas: I did not expect to find you abroad so early.

2 HYLAS.(Realist) It is indeed something unusual; but my thoughts were so taken up with a subject I was discoursing of last night, that finding I could not sleep, I resolved to rise and take a turn in the garden.

3 PHILONOUS. It happened well, to let you see what innocent and agreeable pleasures you lose every morning.
Can there be a pleasanter time of the day, or a more delightful season of the year?
That purple sky, those wild but sweet notes of birds, the fragrant bloom upon the trees and flowers, the gentle influence of the rising sun, these and a thousand nameless beauties of nature inspire the soul with secret transports; its faculties too being at this time fresh and lively, are fit for those meditations, which the solitude of a garden and tranquillity of the morning naturally dispose us to. But I am afraid I interrupt your thoughts: for you seemed very intent on something.

4 HYLAS. It is true, I was, and shall be obliged to you if you will permit me to go on in the same vein; not that I would by any means deprive myself of your company, for my thoughts always flow more easily in conversation with a friend, than when I am alone: but my request is, that you would suffer me to impart my reflexions to you.

5 PHILONOUS. With all my heart, it is what I should have requested myself if you had not prevented me.

6 HYLAS. I was considering the odd fate of those men who have in all ages, through an affectation of being distinguished from the vulgar [archaic: the common people], or some unaccountable turn of thought, pretended either to believe nothing at all, or to believe the most extravagant things in the world.
This however might be borne, if their paradoxes and scepticism did not draw after them some consequences of general disadvantage to mankind.
But the mischief lieth here; that when men of less leisure see them who are supposed to have spent their whole time in the pursuits of knowledge professing an entire ignorance of all things, or advancing such notions as are repugnant to plain and commonly received principles, they will be tempted to entertain suspicions concerning the most important truths, which they had hitherto held sacred and unquestionable.

7 PHILONOUS. I entirely agree with you, as to the ill tendency of the affected doubts of some philosophers, and fantastical conceits of others.
I am even so far gone of late in this way of thinking, that I have quitted several of the sublime notions I had got in their schools for vulgar opinions.
And I give it you on my word; since this revolt from metaphysical notions to the plain dictates of nature and common sense, I find my understanding strangely enlightened, so that I can now easily comprehend a great many things which before were all mystery and riddle.

8 HYLAS. I am glad to find there was nothing in the accounts I heard of you.

9 PHILONOUS. Pray, what were those?

10 HYLAS. You were represented, in last night's conversation, as one who maintained the most extravagant opinion that ever entered into the mind of man, to wit, that there is no such thing as MATERIAL SUBSTANCE in the world.

11 PHILONOUS. That there is no such thing as what PHILOSOPHERS CALL MATERIAL SUBSTANCE, I am seriously persuaded: but, if I were made to see anything absurd or sceptical in this, I should then have the same reason to renounce this that I imagine I have now to reject the contrary opinion.

12 HYLAS. What I can anything be more fantastical, more repugnant to Common Sense, or a more manifest piece of Scepticism, than to believe there is no such thing as MATTER?

13 PHILONOUS. Softly, good Hylas. What if it should prove that you, who hold there is, are, by virtue of that opinion, a greater sceptic, and maintain more paradoxes and repugnances to Common Sense, than I who believe no such thing?

14 HYLAS. You may as soon persuade me, the part is greater than the whole, as that, in order to avoid absurdity and Scepticism, I should ever be obliged to give up my opinion in this point.

15 PHILONOUS. Well then, are you content to admit that opinion for true, which upon examination shall appear most agreeable to Common Sense, and remote from Scepticism?

16 HYLAS. With all my heart. Since you are for raising disputes about the plainest things in nature, I am content for once to hear what you have to say.

17 PHILONOUS. Pray, Hylas, what do you mean by a SCEPTIC?

18 HYLAS. I mean what all men mean--one that doubts of everything.

19 PHILONOUS. He then who entertains no doubts concerning some particular point, with regard to that point cannot be thought a sceptic.

20 HYLAS. I agree with you.
 
kennethamy
 
Reply Wed 24 Mar, 2010 06:45 am
@Humanity,
Humanity;142913 wrote:
I presume you have copies of the Treatise and Dialogs in hand (or folder).

I presume you have copies of the Treatise and Dialogs in hand (or folder).

Let's look at the Dialogs first.
Show me where did Berkeley repeat the phrase Esse est percipi in the Dialog.
If this is his central theme, surely he should have repeated it in the Dialogs.

I have numbered the Dialogs and there are 843 conversational paras.
(have not checked whether i have misnumbered, but i don't think this is critical).

.


It might be worth here to make a distinction made by the late Bernard Williams between the History of Philosophy, and the History of Ideas. He makes this distinction as follows: (As described by John Derbyshire).

Williams distinguishes the 'history of philosophy', which is what he professes to be doing here, from the 'history of ideas'. The history of ideas, in Williams's view, aims at accuracy and authenticity, and proceeds by the scrupulous sifting of sources and the careful establishing of context. In the history of philosophy, by contrast, there is a "cut-off point" at which "authenticity is replaced as the objective by the aim of articulating philosophical ideas".

It looks as if you are discussing the history of ideas, and specifically, Berkeley's. But others are discussing the history of philosophy (in Williams' terms). So, you may not really be disagreeing on anything of substance.
 
wayne
 
Reply Wed 24 Mar, 2010 07:37 am
@kennethamy,
kennethamy;142969 wrote:
It might be worth here to make a distinction made by the late Bernard Williams between the History of Philosophy, and the History of Ideas. He makes this distinction as follows: (As described by John Derbyshire).

Williams distinguishes the 'history of philosophy', which is what he professes to be doing here, from the 'history of ideas'. The history of ideas, in Williams's view, aims at accuracy and authenticity, and proceeds by the scrupulous sifting of sources and the careful establishing of context. In the history of philosophy, by contrast, there is a "cut-off point" at which "authenticity is replaced as the objective by the aim of articulating philosophical ideas".

It looks as if you are discussing the history of ideas, and specifically, Berkeley's. But others are discussing the history of philosophy (in Williams' terms). So, you may not really be disagreeing on anything of substance.


I find your post ,thoughtful and interesting. I am not sure my understanding is correct. I have been thinking about the difference between your style of philosophy and my own. In my readings I tend to lean toward Thoreau, Walton and the like, comparing my ideas directly to experience and observations, thus I find metaphors useful in conveying these ideas. While I see you understand my viewpoint ,your style is very different than my own. Is this the difference you are talking about here?
 
kennethamy
 
Reply Wed 24 Mar, 2010 07:48 am
@wayne,
wayne;142977 wrote:
I find your post ,thoughtful and interesting. I am not sure my understanding is correct. I have been thinking about the difference between your style of philosophy and my own. In my readings I tend to lean toward Thoreau, Walton and the like, comparing my ideas directly to experience and observations, thus I find metaphors useful in conveying these ideas. While I see you understand my viewpoint ,your style is very different than my own. Is this the difference you are talking about here?


I don't think so. It isn't a matter if styles. It is a matter or what your goal is; history of ideas, or the history of philosophy. But there is something else too: philosophy. Simply discussing philosophical problems, and trying to understand and solve them. Here, particular philosophers, or schools of philosophy are only peripheral.
 
wayne
 
Reply Wed 24 Mar, 2010 08:00 am
@kennethamy,
kennethamy;142982 wrote:
I don't think so. It isn't a matter if styles. It is a matter or what your goal is; history of ideas, or the history of philosophy. But there is something else too: philosophy. Simply discussing philosophical problems, and trying to understand and solve them. Here, particular philosophers, or schools of philosophy are only peripheral.


I think I fall into the later category, I am going to do some more work on understanding the first part, it is an distinction I have not heard before. Blame my lacking of education. Smile
 
kennethamy
 
Reply Wed 24 Mar, 2010 08:16 am
@wayne,
wayne;142990 wrote:
I think I fall into the later category, I am going to do some more work on understanding the first part, it is an distinction I have not heard before. Blame my lacking of education. Smile


People have heard of it before, but they still mix the two (or three) things up. Historians of ideas are interested in presenting as clear and accurate an understanding of this or that person (in this case, philosopher) but not particularly interested in examining the particular ideas of the philosopher in terms of whether they are true or false. Others (historians of philosophy) are more interested in analyzing and criticizing the ideas of some particular philosopher (or school of philosophy). Of course, this may be, in part, also a matter of emphasis. You want to get the idea right before you criticize it.
 
Humanity
 
Reply Wed 24 Mar, 2010 07:14 pm
@kennethamy,
kennethamy;142969 wrote:
It might be worth here to make a distinction made by the late Bernard Williams between the History of Philosophy, and the History of Ideas. He makes this distinction as follows: (As described by John Derbyshire).

Williams distinguishes the 'history of philosophy', which is what he professes to be doing here, from the 'history of ideas'. The history of ideas, in Williams's view, aims at accuracy and authenticity, and proceeds by the scrupulous sifting of sources and the careful establishing of context. In the history of philosophy, by contrast, there is a "cut-off point" at which "authenticity is replaced as the objective by the aim of articulating philosophical ideas".

It looks as if you are discussing the history of ideas, and specifically, Berkeley's. But others are discussing the history of philosophy (in Williams' terms). So, you may not really be disagreeing on anything of substance.
The point is Berkeley had been misunderstood throughout the history of philosophy since his days.
In his days, it was not easy to get to read his books and philosophers would rely on others who had read his books.
Someone just picked up the phrase Esse est percipi without understanding it in the whole context and condemn Berkeley merely based on three! words.

Since he is not around to defend what he is accused of, and that there are now opposing views on what his ideas are, the best way to resolve
the issue is to go back to history and find what he really meant.

To do that, what is better than to understand it from the source and investigate what Berkeley really intended to convey.

Whilst we have to get back to history to get the truth of the issue, i have no problem reconciling Berkeley to Kant and the latest knowledge of modern science and others.

Since you and Johnson are the one who misunderstood Berkeley, can you answer the question in the OP.
The purpose of the question in the OP is to ensure we understand Berkeley thoroughly before we critique, agree or disagree with him.
 
mickalos
 
Reply Wed 24 Mar, 2010 08:04 pm
@kennethamy,
kennethamy;142969 wrote:
It might be worth here to make a distinction made by the late Bernard Williams between the History of Philosophy, and the History of Ideas. He makes this distinction as follows: (As described by John Derbyshire).

Williams distinguishes the 'history of philosophy', which is what he professes to be doing here, from the 'history of ideas'. The history of ideas, in Williams's view, aims at accuracy and authenticity, and proceeds by the scrupulous sifting of sources and the careful establishing of context. In the history of philosophy, by contrast, there is a "cut-off point" at which "authenticity is replaced as the objective by the aim of articulating philosophical ideas".

It looks as if you are discussing the history of ideas, and specifically, Berkeley's. But others are discussing the history of philosophy (in Williams' terms). So, you may not really be disagreeing on anything of substance.


My philosophy tutor (of a module titled History of Philosophy from Descartes to Kant, incidentally) told me about an interview he once held, for a position in what I presume was a philosophy faculty, that illustrates this quite well. One of the candidates gave a presentation on some disagreement between Carnap and Heidegger (I think it was on language). At the end of the presentation, which I'm told was very informative, my tutor said, "So, who was right, Heidegger or Carnap?" To which the candidate replied, "Oh, I think it's far too late to say."

I think it's pretty hard to misread Berkeley on this, especially the Dialogues, which is effectively the Treatise for dummies. All that Berkeley means by Esse est percipi is that there is nothing to an object beyond the phenomenal experience of it, no thing in itself as the metaphysical source of one's perceptions.
 
jeeprs
 
Reply Wed 24 Mar, 2010 08:10 pm
@Humanity,
Although as I have pointed out, and I think it was maybe the only valid point I managed to make in the previous thread on this topic, there is a sense in which the interpretation of Berkeley depends on the meaning of the word 'substance'. This is one of those terms which everyone assumes they know the meaning of, but actually has a rather specialised meaning in this context, namely, the Aristotlean:

Quote:
Substance, the first of Aristotle's categories, signifies being as existing in and by itself, and serving as a subject or basis for accidents and accidental changes.
 
Humanity
 
Reply Wed 24 Mar, 2010 08:26 pm
@jeeprs,
jeeprs;143350 wrote:
Although as I have pointed out, and I think it was maybe the only valid point I managed to make in the previous thread on this topic, there is a sense in which the interpretation of Berkeley depends on the meaning of the word 'substance'. This is one of those terms which everyone assumes they know the meaning of, but actually has a rather specialised meaning in this context, namely, the Aristotlean:
Thanks. That is along the concept of what Berkeley meant by 'matter' as corporeal substance introduced by the philosophers.

Berkeley asked Hylas what he meant by 'matter'. i.e.

57 PHILONOUS. I speak with regard to sensible things only.
And of these I ask, whether by their real existence you mean a subsistence exterior to the mind,
and distinct from their being perceived?


To Hylas matter is;
58 HYLAS. I mean a real absolute being, distinct from, and without any relation to, their being perceived.


My expectations to those who are very critical of Bekerley ideas, is whether they understand what Berkeley understood as matter, i.e. corporeal substance and which he denied.

The next question is whether they agree with this definition of matter and whether they accept it as their reality.

If no, what is your own definition of matter.

Kennethamy, Extrain and those who disagree with Berkeley, what is your answer to the above questions.
 
jeeprs
 
Reply Wed 24 Mar, 2010 09:29 pm
@Humanity,
It would help the materialist account if there were actually a definition of matter. I believe that this so far eludes us.
 
Humanity
 
Reply Wed 24 Mar, 2010 09:45 pm
@jeeprs,
jeeprs;143367 wrote:
It would help the materialist account if there were actually a definition of matter. I believe that this so far eludes us.
I written it somewhere.

imo and for this purpose we can deal with 'matter' under the
following categories;

1. Common sense perspective
Matter as in the conventional sense

2. Scientific perpective
Matter as define within the scientific method

3. Philosophical materialism
Matter as described by Hylas, i.e.
58 HYLAS. I mean a real absolute being, distinct from, and without any relation to, their being perceived.


Berkeley agreed with 1 and 2 but not 3.

I believe those who disagree with Berkeley accept 1, 2 and 3, even when they may not be very conscious they are accepting 3.

Are there are other definitions and perspective of matter?
 
mickalos
 
Reply Wed 24 Mar, 2010 10:16 pm
@Humanity,
Humanity;143371 wrote:
I written it somewhere.

imo and for this purpose we can deal with 'matter' under the
following categories;

1. Common sense perspective
Matter as in the conventional sense

2. Scientific perpective
Matter as define within the scientific method

3. Philosophical materialism
Matter as described by Hylas, i.e.
58 HYLAS. I mean a real absolute being, distinct from, and without any relation to, their being perceived.


Berkeley agreed with 1 and 2 but not 3.

I believe those who disagree with Berkeley accept 1, 2 and 3, even when they may not be very conscious they are accepting 3.

Are there are other definitions and perspective of matter?


It's not entirely clear what you mean by the 'scientific perspective' and the 'common sense perspective', the latter is certainly too vague a description for you to say that Berkeley agrees with it. I have no idea what "matter as defined within the scientific method" is supposed to mean, but I would say that the common sense understanding of matter is that matter is the sort of thing that physical objects are made of (although this part of the definition, I grant, sounds rather circular), i.e. wood, stone, paper, and so on, are material things, it persists independently of any perceiver, but it does have phenomenal qualities, it is the metaphysical source of our perceptions; that is to say, something happens when we look at it or touch it, that wouldn't happen if it wasn't there.

Berkeley doesn't agree with this. He thinks that God is the metaphysical source of our perceptions, and he most definitely doesn't think that objects have phenomenal qualities, he thinks that objects are phenomenal qualities! If you take the common sense perspective simply to mean that one's foot doesn't go through a stone when one kicks it, as it might were it a hologram, then, yes, Berkeley agrees, but nobody is going to argue with you on that.
 
kennethamy
 
Reply Wed 24 Mar, 2010 10:29 pm
@mickalos,
mickalos;143348 wrote:
My philosophy tutor (of a module titled History of Philosophy from Descartes to Kant, incidentally) told me about an interview he once held, for a position in what I presume was a philosophy faculty, that illustrates this quite well. One of the candidates gave a presentation on some disagreement between Carnap and Heidegger (I think it was on language). At the end of the presentation, which I'm told was very informative, my tutor said, "So, who was right, Heidegger or Carnap?" To which the candidate replied, "Oh, I think it's far too late to say."

I think it's pretty hard to misread Berkeley on this, especially the Dialogues, which is effectively the Treatise for dummies. All that Berkeley means by Esse est percipi is that there is nothing to an object beyond the phenomenal experience of it, no thing in itself as the metaphysical source of one's perceptions.


Yes, I (of course, agree). And thank you for that delightful anecdote.
 
jeeprs
 
Reply Wed 24 Mar, 2010 10:35 pm
@mickalos,
mickalos;143378 wrote:
He thinks that God is the metaphysical source of our perceptions


It is interesting to contemplate that in the modern framework, 'God' is understood to have 'created' everything in the famous '6 days' at the beginning of time ('in the beginning'.)

There is another interpretation in esoteric philosophy that 'in the beginning' is not actually a temporal description at all, but rather more like 'at the origin of' 'as the source of'. This is sometimes called the idea of 'the ever present origin'. So in this interpretation, God - whatever that might be, and I really think this is something that one should never presume to comprehend - is indeed the metaphysical source of our perceptions, and all else, now.
 
kennethamy
 
Reply Wed 24 Mar, 2010 10:37 pm
@jeeprs,
jeeprs;143350 wrote:
Although as I have pointed out, and I think it was maybe the only valid point I managed to make in the previous thread on this topic, there is a sense in which the interpretation of Berkeley depends on the meaning of the word 'substance'. This is one of those terms which everyone assumes they know the meaning of, but actually has a rather specialised meaning in this context, namely, the Aristotlean:


Yes, it (material substance) does have a specialized philosophical meaning stemming from the ancient Greek "ousia", which Locke famously called, "something I know not what", from which Berkeley argued, in effect, "that's because it is nothing. No wonder it is 'something you know not what'!". But I have been assuming that specialized meaning all along.
 
Humanity
 
Reply Wed 24 Mar, 2010 10:38 pm
@mickalos,
mickalos;143378 wrote:
It's not entirely clear what you mean by the 'scientific perspective' and the 'common sense perspective', the latter is certainly too vague a description for you to say that Berkeley agrees with it. I have no idea what "matter as defined within the scientific method" is supposed to mean, but I would say that the common sense understanding of matter is that matter is the sort of thing that physical objects are made of (although this part of the definition, I grant, sounds rather circular), i.e. wood, stone, paper, and so on, are material things, it persists independently of any perceiver, but it does have phenomenal qualities, it is the metaphysical source of our perceptions; that is to say, something happens when we look at it or touch it, that wouldn't happen if it wasn't there.
In the common sense perspective, matter is defined in whatever manner that is agreed by majority consensus or to specific groups.
The externality of such matter is taken for granted without any debate about it.
It is not even assumed.

Here is how Berkeley viewed matter in the common sense perspective.
839 PHILONOUS. With all my heart: retain the word MATTER,
and apply it to the objects of sense, if you please; provided you do not attribute to them any subsistence distinct from their being perceived.
I shall never quarrel with you for an expression.


The scientific perspective.
In the common sense perspective, we say matter for whatever it is meant to be in accordance to consensus without deliberating it as a concept.
However, from the scientific perspective, whatever is termed 'matter' must be put through the scientific method and peer review.
Science is based on empirical observations, therefore scientist would not put up a scientific theory that there are matter that exist beyond human observations and the scientific method.
They can speculate and hypothesize but it cannot be a scienitific theory until it is observed, tested, repeated under the scientific method and peer-reviewed.

Philosophical Materialism Perspective
If you disagree with Berkeley and you argue about matter in a philosophical setting like this and insist that matter is external and is absolutely independent of mind, then you are probably a philosophical materialist.

So, which perspective is your matter?

Quote:
Berkeley doesn't agree with this. He thinks that God is the metaphysical source of our perceptions, and he most definitely doesn't think that objects have phenomenal qualities, he thinks that objects are phenomenal qualities! If you take the common sense perspective simply to mean that one's foot doesn't go through a stone when one kicks it, as it might were it a hologram, then, yes, Berkeley agrees, but nobody is going to argue with you on that.
This is moot. You misunderstood Berkerley whole scheme of ideas.
I raised the OP to establish exactly what Berkeley agreed or did not agree.

As i had suggested why don't you read Berkeley's two books and we start with what is in the OP and we go from there.
 
mickalos
 
Reply Wed 24 Mar, 2010 11:40 pm
@Humanity,
Humanity;143386 wrote:
In the common sense perspective, matter is defined in whatever manner that is agreed by majority consensus or to specific groups.
The externality of such matter is taken for granted without any debate about it.
It is not even assumed.

Here is how Berkeley viewed matter.
839 PHILONOUS. With all my heart: retain the word MATTER,
and apply it to the objects of sense, if you please; provided you do not attribute to them any subsistence distinct from their being perceived.
I shall never quarrel with you for an expression.


The scientific perspective.
In the common sense perspective, we say matter for whatever it is meant to be in accordance to consensus without deliberating it as a concept.
However, from the scientific perspective, whatever is termed 'matter' must be put through the scientific method and peer review.
Science is based on empirical observations, therefore scientist would not put up a scientific theory that there are matter that exist beyond human observations and the scientific method.
They can speculate and hypothesize but it cannot be a scienitific theory until it is observed, tested, repeated under the scientific method and peer-reviewed.

Philosophical Materialism Perspective
If disagree with Berkeley and you argue about matter in a philosophical setting like this and insist that matter is external and is absolutely independent of mind, then you are probably a philosophical materialist.

So, which perspective is your matter?

How exactly does the scientific method define matter (content-wise rather than method-wise)? Particles with half-integer spin? I'm not sure, I'm not a scientist. Why don't we just say empiricism, which I rather think is Berkeley's point as an empiricist. The point being, all that we observe, by definition, are phenomena.

You seem to be having some issues with the use/mention distinction. Here is the passage you quote in a firmer context, with some emphasis:
HYL. I must needs own, Philonous, nothing seems to have kept me from agreeing with you more than this same MISTAKING THE QUESTION. In denying Matter, at first glimpse I am tempted to imagine you deny the things we see and feel: but, upon reflexion, find there is no ground for it. What think you, therefore, of retaining the name MATTER, and applying it to SENSIBLE THINGS? This may be done without any change in your sentiments: and, believe me, it would be a means of reconciling them to some persons who may be more shocked at an innovation in words than in opinion.

PHIL. With all my heart: retain the word MATTER, and apply it to the objects of sense, if you please; provided you do not attribute to them any subsistence distinct from their being perceived. I shall never quarrel with you for an expression. MATTER, or MATERIAL SUBSTANCE, are terms introduced by philosophers; and, as used by them, imply a sort of independency, or a subsistence distinct from being perceived by a mind: but are never used by common people; or, if ever, it is to signify the immediate objects of sense. One would think, therefore, so long as the names of all particular things, with the TERMS SENSIBLE, SUBSTANCE, BODY, STUFF, and the like, are retained, the word MATTER should be never missed in common talk. And in philosophical discourses it seems the best way to leave it quite out: since there is not, perhaps, any one thing that hath more favoured and strengthened the depraved bent of the mind towards Atheism than the use of that general confused term.


Quite clearly (if you take notice of my own emphasis), if Berkeley were a contemporary philosopher his manner would be "Matter" rather than Matter. In other words he is mentioning the word rather than using it. However, as Berkeley notes, the thing that matter seems to refer to, in its common usage by his contemporaries, is not the sort of thing that Berkeley believes to exist.


How many tails would a dog have if we called legs "tails"? The answer is one, because legs aren't the same thing as tails! The lesson? Just because somebody proposes a new language, you don't have to use it. Hylas is inviting Philonous to speak a new language, Philonous is saying, "Why bother?"



Quote:
This is moot. You misunderstood Berkerley whole scheme of ideas.
I raised the OP to establish exactly what Berkeley agreed or did not agree.

As i had suggest why don't you read Berkeley's two books and we start with what is in the OP and we go from there.
I would hate to suggest that I know more about Berkeley than anybody, even though I often do. Assume that I have read the Dialogues and the Treatise; it's a plausible assumption, I hope. Now, what exactly have I misunderstood about Berkeley's system? I'm pretty sure my post was very much in the spirit of the original post, in that it said what Berkeley agrees with and what Berkeley did not agree with.
 
Humanity
 
Reply Thu 25 Mar, 2010 05:14 am
@kennethamy,
kennethamy;143385 wrote:
Yes, it (material substance) does have a specialized philosophical meaning stemming from the ancient Greek "ousia", which Locke famously called, "something I know not what", from which Berkeley argued, in effect, "that's because it is nothing. No wonder it is 'something you know not what'!". But I have been assuming that specialized meaning all along.


Here is another description of matter.
The word Aristotle uses for matter, ὑλη (hyle or hule), can be literally translated as wood or timber, that is, "raw material" for building.[15] Indeed, Aristotle's conception of matter is intrinsically linked to something being made or composed.
In other words, in contrast to the early modern conception of matter as simply occupying space, matter for Aristotle is definitionally linked to process or change: matter is what underlies a change of substance.

Berkeley's interpretation of matter would be similiar to what is bolded and as per stated by Hylas, i.e.

58 HYLAS. I mean a real absolute being, distinct from, and without any relation to, their being perceived.

---------- Post added 03-25-2010 at 06:30 AM ----------

mickalos;143406 wrote:
How exactly does the scientific method define matter (content-wise rather than method-wise)? Particles with half-integer spin? I'm not sure, I'm not a scientist. Why don't we just say empiricism, which I rather think is Berkeley's point as an empiricist. The point being, all that we observe, by definition, are phenomena.
Science define matter as something that occupy space and have mass. There may other scientific definition for matter, e.g. in QM terms, there is no direct observation, but whatever it is, it must comply within the scientific framework.

The word matter crop up everywhere, therefore we need to be very precise on the term used.

To understand Berkeley we need to understand and agree on he meant by the term 'matter'.



Quote:
You seem to be having some issues with the use/mention distinction. Here is the passage you quote in a firmer context, with some emphasis:

HYL. I must needs own, Philonous, nothing seems to have kept me from agreeing with you more than this same MISTAKING THE QUESTION. In denying Matter, at first glimpse I am tempted to imagine you deny the things we see and feel: but, upon reflexion, find there is no ground for it. What think you, therefore, of retaining the name MATTER, and applying it to SENSIBLE THINGS? This may be done without any change in your sentiments: and, believe me, it would be a means of reconciling them to some persons who may be more shocked at an innovation in words than in opinion.

PHIL. With all my heart: retain the word MATTER, and apply it to the objects of sense, if you please; provided you do not attribute to them any subsistence distinct from their being perceived. I shall never quarrel with you for an expression. MATTER, or MATERIAL SUBSTANCE, are terms introduced by philosophers; and, as used by them, imply a sort of independency, or a subsistence distinct from being perceived by a mind: but are never used by common people; or, if ever, it is to signify the immediate objects of sense. One would think, therefore, so long as the names of all particular things, with the TERMS SENSIBLE, SUBSTANCE, BODY, STUFF, and the like, are retained, the word MATTER should be never missed in common talk. And in philosophical discourses it seems the best way to leave it quite out: since there is not, perhaps, any one thing that hath more favoured and strengthened the depraved bent of the mind towards Atheism than the use of that general confused term.

Quite clearly (if you take notice of my own emphasis), if Berkeley were a contemporary philosopher his manner would be "Matter" rather than Matter. In other words he is mentioning the word rather than using it. However, as Berkeley notes, the thing that matter seems to refer to, in its common usage by his contemporaries, is not the sort of thing that Berkeley believes to exist.

How many tails would a dog have if we called legs "tails"? The answer is one, because legs aren't the same thing as tails! The lesson? Just because somebody proposes a new language, you don't have to use it. Hylas is inviting Philonous to speak a new language, Philonous is saying, "Why bother?"

I would hate to suggest that I know more about Berkeley than anybody, even though I often do. Assume that I have read the Dialogues and the Treatise; it's a plausible assumption, I hope. Now, what exactly have I misunderstood about Berkeley's system? I'm pretty sure my post was very much in the spirit of the original post, in that it said what Berkeley agrees with and what Berkeley did not agree with.
The two quotes i provided was to show how Berkeley viewed matter in the common sense perspective.

That was para 839 of 843 which is near the end and after Berkeley had totally convinced Hylas that matter cannot exist without the involvement of the mind.

Your comment on use/mention distinction is out of context with the other 800 paras of the Dialogues.

Btw, the above is not an excuse, but i am hoping you take a look at B's books seriously and make reference to the relevant points in your discussion.
 
kennethamy
 
Reply Thu 25 Mar, 2010 06:09 am
@Humanity,
Humanity;143450 wrote:

Btw, the above is not an excuse, but i am hoping you take a look at B's books seriously and make reference to the relevant points in your discussion.


Will M. persuade you that he has looked at Berkeley seriously only when he has agreed with you? So it seems.
 
 

 
  1. Philosophy Forum
  2. » Metaphysics
  3. » Berkeley's Treatise and Dialogues As It Is
Copyright © 2024 MadLab, LLC :: Terms of Service :: Privacy Policy :: Page generated in 0.03 seconds on 04/20/2024 at 03:54:40