Did Samuel Johnson misunderstand George Berkeley?

Get Email Updates Email this Topic Print this Page

Reconstructo
 
Reply Sun 7 Mar, 2010 04:44 pm
@Humanity,
Humanity;137064 wrote:

Imo, as far as Kant is concerned, the concept of the noumena is used as a 'wall' to prevent and ensure that the speculations of pure reason are not carried too far to be claimed as objective reality from the back door.
The usual 'thing-in-itself do not exists' because Kant said it is so, is too simplistic.
To really understand this concept and its purpose, we need to comprehend the 90% of the iceberg that support this principle.


Yes, my friend, I understand that. A week ago I was arguing from noumena, but I found myself not satisfied. Kant was right about abuses of pure reason, especially in the cases he attacked. But what is this noumena concept? Does he violate his own rules against pure reason? For what does "noumena" refer to? Nothing, ultimately. It's by definition not a part of our experience, except as the paradoxical concept of that which is not a part of our experience. Kant was a genius, and a leap for philosophy. But there were some kinks in his system. He thought, if I understand him right, that time and causality were transcendental. I think he was wrong on this. I think the analytic can be stripped down to unity and negation. I also think the "transcendental unity of apperception" is an empty concept. I think that Hegel worked out Kant's kinks....by abolishing paradoxical distinctions.

Objectivity is grounded in social practice, not by "noumena" in the least. A world without any sort of consensus would be an utterly subjective world. Instead, we all seem to see the same objects, and we know this because of language, and not because of transcendental idealism. Still, Kant deserves praise. He jumped on all the right issues.
 
Humanity
 
Reply Sun 7 Mar, 2010 10:45 pm
@Reconstructo,
Reconstructo;137308 wrote:
Yes, my friend, I understand that. A week ago I was arguing from noumena, but I found myself not satisfied. Kant was right about abuses of pure reason, especially in the cases he attacked. But what is this noumena concept? Does he violate his own rules against pure reason? For what does "noumena" refer to? Nothing, ultimately. It's by definition not a part of our experience, except as the paradoxical concept of that which is not a part of our experience. Kant was a genius, and a leap for philosophy. But there were some kinks in his system. He thought, if I understand him right, that time and causality were transcendental. I think he was wrong on this. I think the analytic can be stripped down to unity and negation. I also think the "transcendental unity of apperception" is an empty concept. I think that Hegel worked out Kant's kinks....by abolishing paradoxical distinctions.

Objectivity is grounded in social practice, not by "noumena" in the least. A world without any sort of consensus would be an utterly subjective world. Instead, we all seem to see the same objects, and we know this because of language, and not because of transcendental idealism. Still, Kant deserves praise. He jumped on all the right issues.
Yes, Kant was a genius, maybe some sort of intellectual savant.

I noted, to understand and give justification to Kant's ideas, we need to understand every sentence, paragraph, chapter and then the whole book as one idea. I am still trying to get a good grasp of his idea.
Kant's ideas are not wrong in the foolish sense, but they may not be appropriate if we change the perspective, assumptions and circumstances that his ideas were related to.
Thus if we were to discuss the concepts of Kant, e.g. time, space, transcendental, apperception, we need to pick them up with a fine-toothed comb through his Critique of Pure Reason.

As for the concept of the noumena, Kant qualified and had it covered just in case others changed his perspective.
I noted in CoPR, Transcendental doctrine of judgment, (analytic of principles), chapter iii, the ground of the distinction of all objects in general into phenomena and noumena.

Quote:

If by 'noumenon' we mean a thing so far as it is not an object of our sensible intuition, and so abstract from our mode of intuiting it, this is a noumenon in the negative sense of the term.
But if we understand by it an object of a non-sensible intuition, we thereby presuppose a special mode of intuition, namely, the intellectual, which is not that which we possess, and of which we cannot comprehend even the possibility. This would be 'noumenon' in the positive sense of the term...
...........
That, therefore, which we entitle 'noumenon' must be understood as being such only in a negative sense.

Kant insisted that the 'noumenon' must be understood in the negative sense which reconcile with his critique of pure reason, i.e. no objectivity outside our sensible intuition.
 
SammDickens
 
Reply Mon 8 Mar, 2010 09:18 pm
@Pyrrho,
There is much discussion here about whether material objects exist, but there is no need for such discussion. Berkeley would certainly agree that material objects do exist and that they are quite tangible; not like phantoms or illusions. Following Locke, Berkeley agreed that all our knowledge of the world around us comes to us through our perceptions, the experiences of our consciousness. Locke allowed that we never see the things themselves but only the sensory images that impinge upon our consciousness, only ideas as they called them (hence idealism). Berkeley carried this notion to its logical conclusion. If we may only know ideas (we would say sensory images, perhaps) about the world around us, then there is no need that we should hypothesize a kind of existence other than ideas, no need that a material world exist distinct from our perceptions. Ockams Razor (however its spelled!) motivates us to discard what is unnecessary for adequate explanation, so Berkeley declared that "to be is to be perceived" (esse est percipi) because the existence of a kind of reality other than the mind and its ideas (images, perceptions) is not necessary to explain reality. Our world is envisioned in the mind of God, from whence it enters directly into our minds.

Thus when Mr Johnson kicked his tree, it was a real material tree as we know it, and the pangs of his foot were real mental impressions arising from his action; however, all this reality is in essence of the nature of our private dreams, except God dreams much better than we can. All reality as we know it is of the nature of ideas.

Samm
 
Reconstructo
 
Reply Mon 8 Mar, 2010 09:18 pm
@Humanity,
Humanity;137402 wrote:

Kant insisted that the 'noumenon' must be understood in the negative sense which reconcile with his critique of pure reason, i.e. no objectivity outside our sensible intuition.


Yes, and I think it was wise of him. He was a sharp guy. And in many ways it remains a useful concept.
 
Reconstructo
 
Reply Mon 8 Mar, 2010 09:28 pm
@Humanity,
Humanity;137402 wrote:

I noted, to understand and give justification to Kant's ideas, we need to understand every sentence, paragraph, chapter and then the whole book as one idea. I am still trying to get a good grasp of his idea.
Kant's ideas are not wrong in the foolish sense, but they may not be appropriate if we change the perspective, assumptions and circumstances that his ideas were related to.
Thus if we were to discuss the concepts of Kant, e.g. time, space, transcendental, apperception, we need to pick them up with a fine-toothed comb through his Critique of Pure Reason.

I can't claim a "fine-toothed comb" expertise as far as Kant goes. I knew the basics of Kant from various histories-of-philosophy, and then went back to study him closely after exposure to Hegel, especially Hegel via Kojeve.
It wasn't absurd for Kant to declare causality transcendental, as this went with substance being transcendental. And he was right about their relationship. Time, causality, and substance are clearly related. But I think that he was wrong about them being transcendental. It's my opinion that time, causality, and substance, are learned. At the same time unity is transcendental. And so is negation. From these two elements the rest can be built up. Wittgenstein came to the same conclusion in his own words, and also happened to tackle causality as not logically but only psychologically justified. I think that human existence breaks down to the intersection of concepts and the spatial present, and also feelings (a tricky issue). These are just opinions of mine, of course. :bigsmile:
 
jeeprs
 
Reply Mon 8 Mar, 2010 09:32 pm
@SammDickens,
Samm;137769 wrote:
Locke allowed that we never see the things themselves but only the sensory images that impinge upon our consciousness, only ideas as they called them (hence idealism).


I think that Locke was a 'representational realist'. I don't think he said that, I think this is more or less what Berkeley said in response to Locke, whom I am pretty sure, thought that ideas represent objects.
 
SammDickens
 
Reply Mon 8 Mar, 2010 09:47 pm
@kennethamy,
kennethamy;137071 wrote:
Yes, what else could it possibly be? Since if Johnson believed he refuted Berkeley, what else could be the explanation of that except that Johnson did not understand Berkeley?. We needn't even show how he misunderstood Berkeley. His mere disagreement with Berkeley is enough to save us that trouble. (I thought that Pyrrho's quote from Stove was supposed to show that Johnson did misunderstand Berkeley, by the way).

Johnson and Moore did clearly misunderstand Berkeley if they believed their simplistic demonstrations disproved that the underlying nature of reality is that of ideas or perceptions and not some new order of existence having no value in explaining reality. How did they misunderstand Berkley? Berkeley never said the material world, the world of our shared experiences, does not exist. Of course there is a tree and a foot, of course there are two hands. What sort of blithering idiot could deny that what we observe is (usually) real? Berkeley only says that the underlying nature of our observations is like the ideas and perceptions in our minds, and that there is no need to conjecture about some mystical realm beyond our experiences.

Johnson and Moore might as well have looked into the sky and said, "See! The sun does indeed orbit around the earth." In Johnson's case it was perhaps excusable. In Moore's case,...well, was he maybe teaching business school?

Samm

---------- Post added 03-08-2010 at 09:57 PM ----------

jeeprs;137774 wrote:
I think that Locke was a 'representational realist'. I don't think he said that, I think this is more or less what Berkeley said in response to Locke, whom I am pretty sure, thought that ideas represent objects.

I only know that Locke, unlike Berkeley, did not argue that the world had no existence beyond our sensory impressions of it. I also know that Locke, Berkeley, and Hume are the three renowned English Empiricists...or at least that's what they taught me in school. I don't even know if we're disagreeing on this or not. Perhaps I was only too careless in the manner I conveyed some information in my earlier post???

Samm
 
jeeprs
 
Reply Mon 8 Mar, 2010 10:05 pm
@Humanity,
Possibly. It is indeed the case those three are renowned empiricists. But of the three, I think Locke's position was nearest to that of what we would now call 'naive realism'. Although I am quite ready to be corrected on that.

While I'm here, I can't help but note that, in regard to Kant, if

Humanity;137402 wrote:
we need to understand every sentence, paragraph, chapter and then the whole book as one idea


that is a pretty tall order. From my admittedly sketchy reading thus far, it seems that Kant himself is not entirely consistent in his expressions and ideas, and besides, the entire corpus of his writing is regarded as a kind of intellectual Everest in western thought. I think we can learn things from Kant - well I think I have anyway - while still short of this kind of total mastery of his writings.
 
Humanity
 
Reply Tue 9 Mar, 2010 12:08 am
@jeeprs,
Quote:
Originally Posted by Humanity http://www.philosophyforum.com/images/PHBlue/buttons/viewpost.gif
we need to understand every sentence, paragraph, chapter and then the whole book as one idea

jeeprs;137788 wrote:
that is a pretty tall order. From my admittedly sketchy reading thus far, it seems that Kant himself is not entirely consistent in his expressions and ideas, and besides, the entire corpus of his writing is regarded as a kind of intellectual Everest in western thought. I think we can learn things from Kant - well I think I have anyway - while still short of this kind of total mastery of his writings.
Yes, it is indeed a mammoth task.
I am in the process of doing what i'd suggested above.
I hope i can get a better grasp of Kant when i finished with the process.
Prior to this, i have been reading Kant's CoPR off and on over several years but could not grasp and paraphrase his ideas correctly.

Agree, Kant was not consistent with some of the terms he used.
However, we need to note the different context he was using a term.
There are 200+ terms specific only to Kant's ideas and one need to have a Kant dictionary to handle them when reading the book.
 
Humanity
 
Reply Fri 12 Mar, 2010 01:29 am
@Humanity,
Here is a point from Kant to explain why Johnson misunderstood Berkeley.

[QUOTE=Kant in CoPR]
The term 'idealist' is not, therefore, to be understood as applying to those who deny the existence of external objects of the senses,
but only to those who do not admit that their existence is known through immediate perception,
and who therefore conclude that we can never, by way of any possible experience, be completely certain as to their reality. [NKS346]
[/QUOTE]

When Johnson kicked the stone, he was basing on the assumption that Berkeley denied the existence of external objects of the senses.
By kicking the stone, he was trying to prove that the stone exists as an external object independent of his senses.

Berkeley stated very clearly that he did not deny the existence of external objects.
What he asserted was, an unthought matter is an impossibility which is similar to what Kant had stated above.

In Johnson's demonstration, he was merely kicking a 'strawman' based on a mis-understanding, misinterpretation and misrepresentation of Berkeley's idea.

If Johnson had misunderstood Berkeley idea in the first place, it would be impossible for him to refute Berkeley's original idea.
 
kennethamy
 
Reply Fri 12 Mar, 2010 07:11 am
@Humanity,
Humanity;138885 wrote:
Here is a point from Kant to explain why Johnson misunderstood Berkeley.



When Johnson kicked the stone, he was basing on the assumption that Berkeley denied the existence of external objects of the senses.
By kicking the stone, he was trying to prove that the stone exists as an external object independent of his senses.

Berkeley stated very clearly that he did not deny the existence of external objects.
What he asserted was, an unthought matter is an impossibility which is similar to what Kant had stated above.

In Johnson's demonstration, he was merely kicking a 'strawman' based on a mis-understanding, misinterpretation and misrepresentation of Berkeley's idea.

If Johnson had misunderstood Berkeley idea in the first place, it would be impossible for him to refute Berkeley's original idea.


Thank you for that valuable passage from Kant. It is easy to see why Kant wrote that, for he did not want to be counted as an Idealist, and of course Kant did deny the existence of "the external objects of the senses" for, according to Kant, the "external objects of the senses" were but phenomenal, and so, mental and internal. However, Kant did, of course, assert that there was an externality, although it did not consist of external objects of any kind; the noumenon. So, in that quote, Kant is covering himself. Of course, that does not save him from being wrong about Idealism. Berkeley certainly did deny that there were external objects. Although he did not deny that there were physical objects, i.e. the objects of physics. But he did deny that there were material objects, i.e. objects that were not spiritual, i.e. immaterial. (You confuse physical objects, e.g. chairs and tables, which Berkeley affirmed there were, with material objects, which he denied chairs and tables were.

What Johnson did (in part) was to demonstrate that chairs and tables (and stones, of course) were not merely physical objects (which they were) but also material objects.
 
SammDickens
 
Reply Fri 12 Mar, 2010 04:12 pm
@kennethamy,
kennethamy;138931 wrote:
Berkeley certainly did deny that there were external objects. Although he did not deny that there were physical objects, i.e. the objects of physics. But he did deny that there were material objects, i.e. objects that were not spiritual, i.e. immaterial. (You confuse physical objects, e.g. chairs and tables, which Berkeley affirmed there were, with material objects, which he denied chairs and tables were.

What Johnson did (in part) was to demonstrate that chairs and tables (and stones, of course) were not merely physical objects (which they were) but also material objects.

How does Johnson kicking an immaterial tree with his immaterial foot prove the materiality of those physical objects? If he had kicked a tree with his foot in his dreams and had felt the pangs of pain in his dreams as a result of his action, he would not have proven that he was awake. His actions were as pointless as his understanding was faulty.

I believe the distinction of what we call the material world is not that it is external--though it well may be--; rather it is that the world is shared by many of us, that I may see the tree that you see, and a thousand other people may see the tree, and agree that it is a hawthorn tree, and agree upon its estimated height, and agree that its lowest bough was apparently broken off, and that the letters RG+BY have been carved inside a heart symbol about 14 inches below and 11 inches to the right of the broken bough of the tree. And because we share all these details and know them to be consistently apparent over time, we agree that the tree exists exterior (to our own minds). We agree that the idea of the tree, though it be all that we may ever know about it, is not the total reality of the tree, but that something accessible to all our minds is the final reality from which our idea of the tree derives.

Therefore, we say that the reality of the tree is exterior to our minds, not interior as our ideas are. In this sense, the tree would still be exterior (to our minds) even if it originates as an idea in the mind of God. And it will never be verifiable whether the final nature of reality is material or immaterial, so the only distinction of importance is whether reality is exterior/external or interior/internal.

Samm
 
kennethamy
 
Reply Fri 12 Mar, 2010 04:24 pm
@SammDickens,
Samm;139146 wrote:
How does Johnson kicking an immaterial tree with his immaterial foot prove the materiality of those physical objects? If he had kicked a tree with his foot in his dreams and had felt the pangs of pain in his dreams as a result of his action, he would not have proven that he was awake. His actions were as pointless as his understanding was faulty.

I believe the distinction of what we call the material world is not that it is external--though it well may be--; rather it is that the world is shared by many of us, that I may see the tree that you see, and a thousand other people may see the tree, and agree that it is a hawthorn tree, and agree upon its estimated height, and agree that its lowest bough was apparently broken off, and that the letters RG+BY have been carved inside a heart symbol about 14 inches below and 11 inches to the right of the broken bough of the tree. And because we share all these details and know them to be consistently apparent over time, we agree that the tree exists exterior (to our own minds). We agree that the idea of the tree, though it be all that we may ever know about it, is not the total reality of the tree, but that something accessible to all our minds is the final reality from which our idea of the tree derives.

Therefore, we say that the reality of the tree is exterior to our minds, not interior as our ideas are. In this sense, the tree would still be exterior (to our minds) even if it originates as an idea in the mind of God. And it will never be verifiable whether the final nature of reality is material or immaterial, so the only distinction of importance is whether reality is exterior/external or interior/internal.

Samm


But Johnson did not kick an immaterial tree with an immaterial foot. An immaterial foot would have gone right through an immaterial tree, but Johnson's foot did not go through the tree. That is exactly what it means for something to be material, They do not penetrate each other. The one stops the other. People do not kick trees with feet in dreams. What they do is dream they kick trees with feet. (By the way, it was a stone, not a tree). What makes something material is that it exists even when no one believes it exists. It exists even if there are no minds.
 
SammDickens
 
Reply Fri 12 Mar, 2010 05:12 pm
@kennethamy,
kennethamy;139149 wrote:
But Johnson did not kick an immaterial tree with an immaterial foot. An immaterial foot would have gone right through an immaterial tree, but Johnson's foot did not go through the tree. That is exactly what it means for something to be material, They do not penetrate each other. The one stops the other. People do not kick trees with feet in dreams. What they do is dream they kick trees with feet. (By the way, it was a stone, not a tree). What makes something material is that it exists even when no one believes it exists. It exists even if there are no minds.

People may kick trees in dreams and their feet will be stopped by the tree although both are immaterial and imaginary. If Berkeley's reality and its natural laws are composed and maintained in the mind of God, perhaps even in a dream God is having, the tree will continue to exist whether any of our mortal minds are observing it or not. Surely you do not think that if you kick a tree in your dreams, your phantom foot would go right through the phantom tree! Not unless you're having an odd little dream. :whistling: Kicking a tree or stone or dog or habit does not, indeed cannot disprove the Berkeleyan argument that the ultimate nature of reality is ideal.

By the way, what does this mean? "People do not kick trees with feet in dreams. What they do is dream they kick trees with feet." Don't you wish you'd never said that? :bigsmile:

Samm
 
jeeprs
 
Reply Fri 12 Mar, 2010 05:29 pm
@kennethamy,
kennethamy;139149 wrote:
What makes something material is that it exists even when no one believes it exists. It exists even if there are no minds.


This is 'naive realism in a nutshell'. This is described in Wikipedia as
Quote:
world is pretty much as common sense would have it. All objects are composed of matter, they occupy space, and have properties such as size, shape, texture, smell, taste and colour. These properties are usually perceived correctly. So, when we look at and touch things we see and feel those things directly, and so perceive them as they really are. Objects continue to obey the laws of physics and retain all their properties whether or not there is anyone present to observe them doing so."[1]quantum phenomena or with the twin retinal images. This lack of supervenience


(My emphasis)

What Johnson is not getting in all of this, is that the argument is not about the nature of stones. It is about the nature of experience. Johnson assumes that his experience is veridical. He does not turn his attention on himself, and say 'what is the perception of kicking, etc'.

That is why he misunderstands Berkeley.
 
kennethamy
 
Reply Fri 12 Mar, 2010 06:08 pm
@SammDickens,
Samm;139164 wrote:


By the way, what does this mean? "People do not kick trees with feet in dreams. What they do is dream they kick trees with feet." Don't you wish you'd never said that? :bigsmile:

Samm


Of course not. It is true. Dreaming that something happens is not that something happening. If I dream I am in India riding on an elephant, that does not mean that I am in India, riding on an elephant. You know that.

---------- Post added 03-12-2010 at 07:18 PM ----------

jeeprs;139169 wrote:
This is 'naive realism in a nutshell'. This is described in Wikipedia as


(My emphasis)

What Johnson is not getting in all of this, is that the argument is not about the nature of stones. It is about the nature of experience. Johnson assumes that his experience is veridical. He does not turn his attention on himself, and say 'what is the perception of kicking, etc'.

That is why he misunderstands Berkeley.


Although I don't really like the insinuation of the term "naive", since that implies that I am unaware of why people object to direct realism, I don't really mind being called a naive realist, since I think that naive realism (with the qualifications I just mentioned) is substantially true.

It is, after all true that if the stone and the foot were both immaterial, the foot would go through the stone. But that didn't happen. Or do you think that it did happen, but it escaped notice?

The argument is not about experience. It is, as you point out, about how experience is caused. The most reasonable explanation I know of is that our experience is caused by material bodies. Have you a better explanation?
 
SammDickens
 
Reply Fri 12 Mar, 2010 08:40 pm
@kennethamy,
kennethamy;139174 wrote:
Of course not. It is true. Dreaming that something happens is not that something happening. If I dream I am in India riding on an elephant, that does not mean that I am in India, riding on an elephant. You know that.

Suppose that you are dreaming a really vivid dream about riding an elephant in India. How do you know you are dreaming? You don't. Suppose that the nature of your existence in this world is like the nature of a really vivid dream insofar as it is all in your mind, insofar as it is all of the character of mental image like our dreams. In fact, it is of the character of mental images because our experiences are not immediate; as we are aware of some experiences our senses are in-taking another set of experiences that will process through the brain to our consciousness. The same experiences that enter our consciousness from sensory experience could as well enter our consciousness from our imagination or from dreams.

Samm
 
Humanity
 
Reply Fri 12 Mar, 2010 09:31 pm
@kennethamy,
kennethamy;138931 wrote:
Thank you for that valuable passage from Kant. It is easy to see why Kant wrote that, for he did not want to be counted as an Idealist, and of course Kant did deny the existence of "the external objects of the senses" for, according to Kant, the "external objects of the senses" were but phenomenal, and so, mental and internal. However, Kant did, of course, assert that there was an externality, although it did not consist of external objects of any kind; the noumenon. So, in that quote, Kant is covering himself. Of course, that does not save him from being wrong about Idealism. Berkeley certainly did deny that there were external objects. Although he did not deny that there were physical objects, i.e. the objects of physics. But he did deny that there were material objects, i.e. objects that were not spiritual, i.e. immaterial. (You confuse physical objects, e.g. chairs and tables, which Berkeley affirmed there were, with material objects, which he denied chairs and tables were.
What Johnson did (in part) was to demonstrate that chairs and tables (and stones, of course) were not merely physical objects (which they were) but also material objects.
Kant in his Critique wrote a chapter on "The refutation of Idealism" to contrast his 'Transcendental Idealism' from Berkeley's 'Dogmatic Idealism'.

Despite the differentiation, both Kant and Berkeley in general are Idealist of the same mould with slight variations.
Both believe that physical objects have external existence in the common sense perspective, but do not have absolute existence without taking the 'mind' into consideration.
In a way, both will admit they are naive realists from the common sense perspective, but being good philosophers they had the intellectual foresignt to challenge the prevailing majority view then.

Kant's statement on what Idealist believes is applicable to Berkeley.
I am highlighting this because i know there was a misunderstanding of Berkeley's idealism based on a 'strawman' of immaterialism. i.e.

wiki wrote:

Immaterialism is the theory propounded by Bishop Berkeley in the 18th century which holds that there are no material objects, only minds and ideas in those minds.


Having read Berkeley's Treatise, i am very confident that the above is a wrong interpretation of Berkeley's idea.
Berkeley was too intelligent to propound such a stupid theory as stated by the 'strawman' above.

The core ideas of all known idealists is fundamentally to expand the narrow views of common sense and to counter the philosophical realists' view that reality is absolutely independent of mind.

Johnson misinterpretated Berkeley that material objects exists only as ideas in mind, and wrongly basing on the container metaphor.

If Johnson and Berkeley were to meet face to face, I ams sure Berkeley would have told Johnson the following;

Berkeley to Johnson:
"Don't be stupid, I believe the stone in front of me exists external to myself as we normally understand within the common sense.
If I kicked the stone, i will feel the solidness of the stone and possible pain.
But for you (Johnson) to believe that the stone exists absolutely independent of the observer is philosophical doubtful.
My philosophical answer to this is, .................... ideas, mind, god and blah blah blah..
 
jeeprs
 
Reply Fri 12 Mar, 2010 09:58 pm
@kennethamy,
kennethamy;139174 wrote:
Although I don't really like the insinuation of the term "naive", since that implies that I am unaware of why people object to direct realism, I don't really mind being called a naive realist, since I think that naive realism (with the qualifications I just mentioned) is substantially true.


Well I am pleased about that because I don't see it as pejorative and it wasn't meant as such. It is as you say a philosophical outlook, and probably the 'default' one, for most people.

kennethamy;139174 wrote:
It is, after all true that if the stone and the foot were both immaterial, the foot would go through the stone. But that didn't happen. Or do you think that it did happen, but it escaped notice?


Consider it as follows: it is not an 'imaginary' stone in the sense of an object that only appears to be there, like a holographic projection, that is kicked with an imaginary foot. I can understand why one would imagine that, but that is not the argument. The argument is that when we kick the stone, we experience the sensation of kicking, and the sensation of the stone moving. We don't experience anything other than these sensations. Without sensations we can't be said to have perceived anything. So do we have two things? The stone and the sensation of the stone? Actually, we don't. Whenever we have contact with the stone, whether visual or tactile, what we have is the sensation of the stone.

Now is there a stone apart from the sensation? You always insist there is, but where is the stone? Why, there is it! And when you gesture towards it, and I look at it, I experience the visual sensation of seeing the stone, as we both do. It is no stone without sensation, and no sensation without stone.

kennethamy;139174 wrote:
The argument is not about experience. It is, as you point out, about how experience is caused. The most reasonable explanation I know of is that our experience is caused by material bodies. Have you a better explanation?


So the whole argument is that it is finally not possible to separate the experience from the cause of the experience. The object and my seeing it (or kicking it) actually comprises a unitary whole of I-seeing-it. There is no 'it' outside of the seeing of it. It is exactly an argument about the nature of experience.

But this does not mean that a thing does not exist when not seen. In this scenario we are envisaging its imagined non-existence. But whether we imagine the stone as present, or absent, both these are acts of our imagination. By imagining its non-existence, we are saying 'well that is absurd, if nothing is perceived then it would not exist', on the basis of our imagination of its non-existence.

But in all of this we are not seeing anything outside our own experience of the world. And indeed we never to.

Berkeley's argument in Dialogs clarifies this further by the following examples. This rock - is it large or small? Why, small. But insects have eyes, do they not? They do. So if they see the rock, is it large or small? Why, to them, it is very large, no doubt.

So is it really large, or is it really small?

What color is it? It appears grey, like granite. Look at it under a microscope. What color is it then? Why, it appears multi-hued, with many gold specs in it. So is it really grey, or is it really multi-hued?

And so on.
 
kennethamy
 
Reply Fri 12 Mar, 2010 11:59 pm
@SammDickens,
Samm;139200 wrote:
Suppose that you are dreaming a really vivid dream about riding an elephant in India. How do you know you are dreaming? You don't. Suppose that the nature of your existence in this world is like the nature of a really vivid dream insofar as it is all in your mind, insofar as it is all of the character of mental image like our dreams. In fact, it is of the character of mental images because our experiences are not immediate; as we are aware of some experiences our senses are in-taking another set of experiences that will process through the brain to our consciousness. The same experiences that enter our consciousness from sensory experience could as well enter our consciousness from our imagination or from dreams.

Samm


But how I know I am dreaming is an entirely different issue from the point I made that when I am dreaming, what I am dreaming is happening is not happening. I agree that there is the problem of whether we can know whether we are dreaming (although I don't think it is a serious problem) but the fact remains that dreams are not reality, and that when I am dreaming I am in India, I am at home in the United States.

---------- Post added 03-13-2010 at 01:18 AM ----------

Humanity;139205 wrote:
Kant in his Critique wrote a chapter on "The refutation of Idealism" to contrast his 'Transcendental Idealism' from Berkeley's 'Dogmatic Idealism'.

Despite the differentiation, both Kant and Berkeley in general are Idealist of the same mould with slight variations.
Both believe that physical objects have external existence in the common sense perspective, but do not have absolute existence without taking the 'mind' into consideration.
In a way, both will admit they are naive realists from the common sense perspective, but being good philosophers they had the intellectual foresignt to challenge the prevailing majority view then.

Kant's statement on what Idealist believes is applicable to Berkeley.
I am highlighting this because i know there was a misunderstanding of Berkeley's idealism based on a 'strawman' of immaterialism. i.e.



Having read Berkeley's Treatise, i am very confident that the above is a wrong interpretation of Berkeley's idea.
Berkeley was too intelligent to propound such a stupid theory as stated by the 'strawman' above.

The core ideas of all known idealists is fundamentally to expand the narrow views of common sense and to counter the philosophical realists' view that reality is absolutely independent of mind.

Johnson misinterpretated Berkeley that material objects exists only as ideas in mind, and wrongly basing on the container metaphor.

If Johnson and Berkeley were to meet face to face, I ams sure Berkeley would have told Johnson the following;

Berkeley to Johnson:
"Don't be stupid, I believe the stone in front of me exists external to myself as we normally understand within the common sense.
If I kicked the stone, i will feel the solidness of the stone and possible pain.
But for you (Johnson) to believe that the stone exists absolutely independent of the observer is philosophical doubtful.
My philosophical answer to this is, .................... ideas, mind, god and blah blah blah..


Berkeley's intelligence (or lack of it) is not relevant to what he believed. He attacks materialism over and over again, and, it is his view, materialism is an illusion wrought by the Devil to conceal God from people, since when it is realized that materialism is false, and immaterialism is true, it will be clear that since the world is spiritual, and nothing material can be the cause of what is spiritual, only God could be the cause of the world. So, the immaterialism of the world is Berkeley's argument for God.

Berkeley never held that material objects exist only as ideas in the mind I(whatever that might mean). Berkeley held that there were no material objects. There were physical objects, chairs, stones, stars, but their esse was percipi, (their existence was to be perceived). Like all other Idealists, Berkeley confused what something is, with how it is known. In fact, that confusion is the foundation of Idealism. It is the confusion of metaphysics with epistemology.
 
 

 
Copyright © 2024 MadLab, LLC :: Terms of Service :: Privacy Policy :: Page generated in 0.12 seconds on 12/23/2024 at 07:07:51