@kennethamy,
kennethamy wrote:The central point to keep in mind is not to confuse the possibility of being mistaken with the actuality of being mistaken.
Not all cases have a referent "truth". That is, "actuality" is contextual;
this is the central point I believe we should keep in mind.
An example where referent truth is present:
The capital legislation is exactly what I was referring to in my above post when I mentioned fixed logical systems that define "truth". In the legislation case, we have a record kept that is defined as "truth". Any schmuck with a 2 dollar city map can claim the capital of Ecuador is "Jinglefuck", but
he would be wrong as the recorded "truth" of "Quito" is intersubjectively agreed upon. Intersubjective agreement is imperative in this case.
An example where referent truth is not present:
If my wife removed the vase 178 times during her cleaning process, she, in all practicality, wouldn't have kept a record. At work, despite this, I would say I know the vase is on the table. This means that even if my boss asked me at 3:34 if the vase was on the table, and I said "Yes, I know the vase is on the table", without knowing the vase wasn't going to be replaced on the table until 3:35, I would still be content with saying "I know...". This is because for all practical purposes the "know" in this context is a form of
probability. The "truth" here is dynamic by it's very nature.
An example where referent truth is present, but "knowledge" is questionable:
A great majority of things we regard as scientific knowledge. The example I gave with Mars may sound farfetched, but I'm confident instances like these have occurred in the past. Particularly, as I noted, the "squaring the circle" problem. But, just to throw the example out there again: If scientists, through our
current methods, deem Mars to be made of rock, can we not say this is scientific knowledge? Surely it would have to be intersubjectively agreed upon by scientists. Science is a method, so we do, by definition, have something to reference "truth" by - to a probability. If we regard Mars being made of rock as scientific knowledge, and then the human species discovers Mars is made of playdo 500 years from now, what then? Here we have "knowledge" being questioned and a referent truth present; we have what we at least
think to be actuality.
So, when we just say, "Knowledge is JTB (Justified True Belief)", what are we actually saying? Is "truth" being considered from differing contexts?
ABC wrote:Some people can strongly believe things on little or no evidence. Suppose someone is utterly convinced that the Earth is only 6,000 years old. They think they have ample justification for this view, whereas we think they have none. Must we say that they know it is true, but that we know it is false? What determines whether we attribute to a person (a) non-objective knowledge or (b) mere belief - is it the observed strength of the person's belief, or the observed strength of their evidence?
ABC, please read above as this will also help our conversation.
To answer you, though: The case you brought up would be decided on intersubjective agreement. "Truth", in this case, does have a reference (see my last example), and those who work with the method (whatever science-related field) would come to a conclusion. The conclusion with the most authority we would deem scientific "knowledge".
That person, though, through his own methods (likely to be scientific in nature) has the potential to prove the earth is 6,000 years old. It's
possible(not likely) that he could undermine all the research we've done on the aging of this planet and present a new case. If that case became popularized enough, we could deem that "knowledge". Hasn't this how things have always worked?
Besides the innerworkings of one's mind, if one mutters "knowledge", there is justification needed. So, belief, of course, isn't the only necessity.
But, keeping in mind, that truth is muddy without clarification.