Get Email Updates • Email this Topic • Print this Page
You're not suggesting to me that it's so obvious to you. I wasn't giving you those criticisms and thought-experiments to highlight common knowledge. I went through all that rigmarole to indicate to you that your argument is insufficient, non-explanatory, and false.
Here's another distinction that comes into play. When I believe something, it may be the result of reflection, a process that culminates in my reaching a point of persuasion. In other cases, it can be the result of an immediate realization (or assumption). Not sure how that will affect the analysis of necessary and sufficient conditions that nerdfiles is proposing, but here's an example.
1. Someone tells me there is a snake in my tool shed. I don't believe a snake could possibly get in there, so I refuse to believe it. Next time I go into my tool shed, I hear a rustling noise. I still don't believe it's a snake. Next time I go in there, I see a snake skin. Now I say, "Yep, there's a snake in the shed." Necessary and sufficient conditions involved an accumulation of evidences, none of which actually proves that indeed there is a snake in the shed. (I may be wrong. My friend may have even put the snake skin in there to trick me, but counter evidence doesn't occur to me.)
2. I open the door to my shed, and when I move a box, am startled by the very brief sight of something long and slender, that apparently disappears under another box. "Oh, my gosh! There's a snake in my shed!" Now, in jostling around the boxes, and considering the clutter of hoses and tubes, it's entirely possible that my "sight" of a snake was actually an optical illusion. But I don't stop to reflect on other possibilities, because my "sighting" was so vivid. I really believe I saw a snake.
I don't know if, indeed, there is an ultimate difference, but it seems to me that necessary and sufficient conditions for a belief can be very different depending on whether I have thought something through, and have weighed the evidence, or whether I have had one distinct sensory experience.
1. Someone tells me there is a snake in my tool shed. I don't believe a snake could possibly get in there, so I refuse to believe it. Next time I go into my tool shed, I hear a rustling noise. I still don't believe it's a snake. Next time I go in there, I see a snake skin. Now I say, "Yep, there's a snake in the shed." Necessary and sufficient conditions involved an accumulation of evidences, none of which actually proves that indeed there is a snake in the shed. (I may be wrong. My friend may have even put the snake skin in there to trick me, but counter evidence doesn't occur to me.)
Your snake example seems to pass, but is seeing vividly a condition we want to hold as necessary for saying someone believes that something is the case?
It seems to me that what you are showing by your examples is that it is possible for you to be mistaken when, on the basis of sense-perception, you believe something to be true...
Are you implying that it is necessary to have justification to believe at all? It seems that you are saying (positive) justification is presupposed by belief.
Perhaps we should make a distinction clear: to have a reason for believing is not the same as having a justification for believing.
What would be a justification for believing the world is round, if your example falters?
I can't think of any justifications - I can only think of reasons why I do believe it is round.
I think that by "reason" you mean, "cause". That is, the explanation of your believing the world is round. But by "justification" is meant the grounds (or the reasons) for believing the world is round. As for example, that astronauts can see that it is round, and satellite pictures show it is round. Of course, astronomers have other reasons or justification for believing the world is round. A justification, or a reason, may cause you to believe that the world is round too. So a justification or reason may also be a cause. So, also, a person's reason for doing something may also be a cause of his doing that thing. Someone may ask me why I crossed the street. I might answer, because I saw Fred across the street, and I wanted to talk to him. I am giving my reason for crossing the street, and also the cause of my crossing the street all at once. A reason for doing something can be understood as a belief and a desire. In my case, my reason for crossing the street was that I, 1. believed that Fred was across the street, and, 2. I desired to talk to Fred.
The term "reason" is ambiguous as between, a causal explanation, and justification. If someone asks A, "why do you believe in God?", A might reply:
1. Because I was reared in an extremely religious household, or,
2. Because the universe must come from something, and only God could create a universe.
1. is obviously a causal explanation, but not a justification.
2. is obviously a justification, but not (usually) a causal explanation.
Both might be called, A's "reasons" for believing in God.
But, we should note also that sometimes a justification may also be a causal explanation for why someone believes in God. It might be that A was an atheist until someone told him 2. above, and that justification might also be the causal explanation of his belief in God.
But more usually, the justification for my belief is not the causal explanation of my belief.
Beliefs always (I suppose) have some cause. But some beliefs are held without any, or very inadequate, justification.
Yes, so, as I said, reason (causal explanation) can sometimes be justification (but in your case, not usually). I don't think we should use reason and justification interchangeably, though. It seems better to distinguish, now that all participants in this conversation understand the "reason" we're referring.
.
I think that we should keep "reason" for "justification", and if we mean, "cause" or "causal explanation", that is what we should say. Remembering, at the same time, that reasons (justifications) can sometimes also be causes (of beliefs).
Right. A justification may make the belief for you. One might say, "You don't really believe it unless you can justify it, even if minimally." But when I speak of "causing to belief" I mean something to the effect "being the cause which makes that belief possible."
If you never take maths or get introduced to any sort of it, your belief that 2+2=4 will be non-existence. Teachers, etc make that belief possible. They are causes, in a sense, but they're not justifications.
But even then, a justification does not "cause" you to believe that p like "cause" in the "makes possible" sense, or "makes probable" (a really good teacher).
Justifications are reasons for believing it. To speak of "justification as causes for belief" would just be to mean "justifications are reasons for believing some such proposition."
It's not that reasons themselves can be causes. It's that the word "reason" has a connotation which overlaps with a connotation of the word "cause," and thus they can be used in some cases interchangeably. But these words do have connotations which are mutually exclusive.
If Jimmy believes everything his teacher tells him, then Jimmy's teacher's telling him that the earth is round is the cause, as well as the reason, as well as Jimmy's justification for Jimmy's belief that the earth is round.
We, looking at Jimmy's naivete, would say, "Jimmy, we understand what prompted you to believe it, and we understand why you believe it, but your belief is not adequately justified." But that is due to our more sophisticated and multiple justifications for our belief that that earth is round.
In the final analysis, though, our belief that the earth is round is not that much different than Jimmy's (assuming none of us has actually conducted or directly observed scientific experiments that demonstrate its roundness). He cites one authority. We cite several or many, and add evidence available to us from second-hand sources.
Yes, a justification need not be an adequate justification. But, why isn't it an adequate justification of our belief that Earth is round that reliable authorities tell us it is? Most of what we know is justified by authority, and it is up to us to make sure that the authority is reliable...
Well, just as the adequacy of any justification is subject to debate, so also is the reliability of any authority. Right?