@paulhanke,
paulhanke wrote:... that reminds me of something Popper once said: that science's search for truth can never end - that even if science happens to stumble upon an objective truth, it has no way to verify this and thus will continue the search ... I think your definition of knowledge has this same quality - that even if you were to stumble upon knowledge, you have no way of removing all doubt that you could be mistaken (as observed by Popper, science may not even be able to help you here!) and thus can at best only believe you have discovered knowledge ... in which case it seems that the title of this thread has significant validity.
But does your definition of knowledge jibe with common usage of the word? ... does it jibe with the concept of a "body of knowledge"? ... does it jibe with the DIKW heirarchy?
The fact that I might be mistaken (as I have pointed out) does not show I do not know. Only if it can be shown that I am mistaken, can it be shown that I do not know. Consider this conversation:
A. I know that Quito is the capital of Ecuador.
B. But you might be mistaken.
A. Yes, but do you think that I am mistaken
B. No, I believe you are right. It is the capital. I was there just other day.
A. So, you think I do know that Quito is the capital.
B. No I do not?
A. But why, you say you believe it is the capital.
B. Yes, but you might be mistaken.
A. ??????
The "body of knowledge" is what people know. That is, believe, and their belief is both true and justified. So why does it not jibe?
As for Popper, somewhere in his, "Conjectures and Refutations" he draws the following analogy:
A mountain climber is trying to get to the summit of a mountain. He believes he has reached the summit, and from his calculations he is justified in believing he has reached the summit. But where he stands is shrouded in clouds, so he cannot tell he has reached the summit. Nevertheless, he has reached the summit, He is right in believing he has.
Now, Popper says, that mountain climber knows he has reached the summit. He believes he has. He is justified in believing he has. And it is true that he has.
The mountain climber does not have to know that he knows he has reached the summit, in order to know he has reached the summit. Indeed, on the contrary, he has to know he has reached the summit in order to know that he knows he has reached the summit.