Get Email Updates • Email this Topic • Print this Page
Oh, please quito ready.
Here are some subjective qualities, and not a complete list: Infinites, existence, God, justice, social and political equality, freedom, loudness, intelligence, and ambivalence. If a thing is an object, even like the moon in the sky it is an object of sense. Sense tells us that it is, and knowledge tells us what it is, and its relationship to our own life gives it its meaning.
What do you consider the difference is between belief and knowledge. I trust it is certainty and veracity. But knowledge is never complete, and belief seeks completeness without knowledge. Still one can know a thing short of being able to prove a thing. Before it was possible for a monkey to know a lion as an objective reality, to give any precision to its beliefs regarding those jaws of death, or to be able to describe it in detail, or talk about it; it still knew what a lion was. Knowledge is judgement and we can often judge a thing without consciously or critically doing so. If you know a leaf is green no amount of consequential knowledge to the opposite will sway you. So what if colors are green? We look at vegetation and see green. The conclusion can then be made that all that is green is vegetation, and since that means life to us we like it.
To everybody:):
I would like to reiterate Locke's position,
It was John Locke's position that when we perceive objects we do not perceive the objects as they are said to exist in themselves.
John Locke states that what we perceive are rather, ideas (modern writers speak of " sense-data" or "sensa" or "percepts") not physical objects. Whether or not the sense-data resemble the physical objects to which they are believed to "correspond" in some sense, they are at any rate distinct from them. This philosophical theory is commonly called (epistemological) dualism.
According to Locke, who held a special form of this theory, we are mistaken in supposing that to all the qualities of our sense-data there correspond similar qualities in the objects. Colours, for example, correspond to certain arrangements of the molecules at the surfaces of physical objects by virtue of which the latter reflect light of a particular wave length into the eyes of sentient organisms, but such structures do not resemble sensations of colour. The apparently brown penny "as it is in itself" does not have a colour nor a degree of temperature at all, any more than the fire has a quality resembling the pain it produces!
On the other hand, said Locke, ideas of shape and size and motion and weight do correspond to similar properties of physical objects. The penny may not have that particular shape which it appears to have under certain conditions, but it does have a shape; and it may not have the particular size it appears to have from such and such a distance (it certainly could not have all the apparent sizes, for that would contradict the assumption of constancy of size), but it does have a size. Those qualities which are in the objects themselves, he called "primary," and those which only characterize our sense-data he called "secondary."
To everybody:):
I would like to reiterate Locke's position,
It was John Locke's position that when we perceive objects we do not perceive the objects as they are said to exist in themselves.
John Locke states that what we perceive are rather, ideas (modern writers speak of " sense-data" or "sensa" or "percepts") not physical objects. Whether or not the sense-data resemble the physical objects to which they are believed to "correspond" in some sense, they are at any rate distinct from them. This philosophical theory is commonly called (epistemological) dualism.
According to Locke, who held a special form of this theory, we are mistaken in supposing that to all the qualities of our sense-data there correspond similar qualities in the objects. Colours, for example, correspond to certain arrangements of the molecules at the surfaces of physical objects by virtue of which the latter reflect light of a particular wave length into the eyes of sentient organisms, but such structures do not resemble sensations of colour. The apparently brown penny "as it is in itself" does not have a colour nor a degree of temperature at all, any more than the fire has a quality resembling the pain it produces!
On the other hand, said Locke, ideas of shape and size and motion and weight do correspond to similar properties of physical objects. The penny may not have that particular shape which it appears to have under certain conditions, but it does have a shape; and it may not have the particular size it appears to have from such and such a distance (it certainly could not have all the apparent sizes, for that would contradict the assumption of constancy of size), but it does have a size. Those qualities which are in the objects themselves, he called "primary," and those which only characterize our sense-data he called "secondary."
To everybody:):
I would like to reiterate Locke's position,
It was John Locke's position that when we perceive objects we do not perceive the objects as they are said to exist in themselves.
John Locke states that what we perceive are rather, ideas (modern writers speak of " sense-data" or "sensa" or "percepts") not physical objects. Whether or not the sense-data resemble the physical objects to which they are believed to "correspond" in some sense, they are at any rate distinct from them. This philosophical theory is commonly called (epistemological) dualism.
According to Locke, who held a special form of this theory, we are mistaken in supposing that to all the qualities of our sense-data there correspond similar qualities in the objects. Colours, for example, correspond to certain arrangements of the molecules at the surfaces of physical objects by virtue of which the latter reflect light of a particular wave length into the eyes of sentient organisms, but such structures do not resemble sensations of colour. The apparently brown penny "as it is in itself" does not have a colour nor a degree of temperature at all, any more than the fire has a quality resembling the pain it produces!
On the other hand, said Locke, ideas of shape and size and motion and weight do correspond to similar properties of physical objects. The penny may not have that particular shape which it appears to have under certain conditions, but it does have a shape; and it may not have the particular size it appears to have from such and such a distance (it certainly could not have all the apparent sizes, for that would contradict the assumption of constancy of size), but it does have a size. Those qualities which are in the objects themselves, he called "primary," and those which only characterize our sense-data he called "secondary."
What we know are Ideas, and ideas are what we know. Qualities are what we perceive, and what we perceive are qualities, (properties). The hard part is that many objects are not simple objects consisting of a single quality as a simple idea, but are conceptual manifolds. To know a penny one must know the idea of the penny, but to know it as an idea is to understand what it may seem like in every circumstance, which is every kind of quality it has plus every variable of quality. Pennies are easy. Things in nature like leaves are complex by another magnitude of complexity. How many qualities of color might a leaf demonstrate in time? How might its location or weight or shape or temperature change?
We recognize things by their qualities. When we have recognized enough qualities we imagine what concept the object belongs to, and rightly or wrongly account that we know its character. Do we see things by their qualities? Absolutely, in my opinion, since we see, perceive, qualities. When we understand the nature of our qualities we can compare them as quanitites. When we do not understand them we can still perceive them. If a coin warms to the touch as gold does, or a copper coin does more slowly than gold we can say we undertand something of its character even if the means to objectively compare coins is beyond our ability.
Ultimately complete knowledge is beyond all of us. As we learn more we change the concept we know by, and the process will never be complete. If knowledge is incomplete, and the concept is incomplete it is because our ideas stand far beyond our ability to verify. We always know more than we can prove. Concepts have always outstripped the ability of science to test them for truth, just as insight has always beat knowledge in a fair race.
What is called primary and secondary qualities corespond to objective and subjective judgements about some thing. Yet, since primary qualities rest upon scientific method and instraments resulting from our understanding of individual qualities, they will only be less subjective and more objective.
I have never known an Idea in my life, and neither, I must, admit have I ever known a penny, save in the sense that if someone asks me whether I know that penny, meaning, do I recognize that penny. But except in that sense, "knowing a penny" is not a English phrase.
What I do know are true statements or propositions (although, alas!,not all of them). I know, for instance, the statement or proposition that Quito is the capital of Ecuador. I am not at all sure what you mean by the term "idea" (or "Idea" as you spelled it) since that term has a number of meanings. In philosophy it sometimes means something like "concept", and sometimes what has been called a "sense-datum". I do have (I hope) concepts like the concept of a capital of a country, and if there are such entities as sense-data, I suppose I have had a few of those too. But I have never known either a concept or a sense-datum.
Bertrand Russell held that the sense in which I "know" my sense-data (or, I suppose, concepts) is what he called, "knowledge by acquaintance". Namely, I am "acquainted" (aware?) of my concepts and sense-data (if there are any such things).
P.S. I am really not clear what you might mean by "complete knowledge", so I am just guessing. But I guess that I "completely" know that Quito is the capital of Ecuador. Do you have any reason to object to that?
If you can recognize a penny it is because you know a penny, and you know when you grasp the concept, and no one ever completely grasps the concept without objective knowledge of the object in question.
False. You can make true statements about what you know, but I would argue, that you know more than you can be certain is true. Idea, form, notion, concept, image all sort of point to the same understanding. I don't think people know concepts, but know with concepts. Every word in the dictionary is a concept because each is a bit of knowledge that can be defined and used to build a greater sense of understanding. Was is seldom possible with a dictionary definition is to reference the concept to the reality represented. And, just as with other concepts, each time a word is used it is redefined, so concepts are never complete, and concepts never have all the knowledge each is capable of holding. We can always learn more of finite objective reality.
For example I learned what identity and conservation were while trying to define them myself without a word. If I had learned the words as a concept, and the definition of the words, I may have been able by aquaintance to identify identity and conservation. I don't think a person gets the concept really until the have seen the object conceptualized as an object in reality. Finite Objective Knowledge is what concepts are made of, and learning the concept before the object is a short cut to knowledge, but by itself does not give anyone the ability to make rational judgements. If a concept means that a person has visited an object before, and made critical judgements in regard to it, then, I, going with information in hand to the same object may learn faster, and take it a step further.
I would suggest that as a sort of meaningless bit of information, by itself. Unless one knows everthing essential to placing Quito on a map and globe and understanding the relationship of capital to other cities, who lives there, why they live there, if there is a there there, where it is from here, and etc. I think it is entirely possible to learn about Quito to the point were one can make true statements in regard to it. No matter how one tries, one will never know all there is to know about Quito, or any other subject. We can know enough. We can know some. And we can know more than we can usually prove. Just as reality overlaps truth completely, as all thing that are true are also real, -truth completely covers knowledge. If we know something it is because it is true whether we can prove it or not. If it is false knowledge it is not knowledge at all. If truth must be verifyable it will always wait on greater knowledge still.
The reality of truth is this: Truth is not always true, and so not always truth because like all concepts it is a form of relationship. Some times to have the relationship we must agree that what is not true is true, even when we know better. If the point of truth is lonliness then tell me another lie. It will be easier to swallow if I wash it down with a beer. File this last part if you find it confusing.
I cannot "know" objects save in the sense of recognizing them. What I can know are propositions or statements about objects. For instance, I can know that the ball is red, or that there is a table in the next room. But I cannot "know" a table, nor can I "know" a ball.
I never have claimed to be certain about anything. By "certain" I mean know without the possibility of error. That would amount to infallibility, and I have never claimed to be infallible since "to err is human". But I (and you) know a great many things. I know that water is H20; that Mars is the fourth planet from the Sun, and, yes, that Quito is the capital of Ecuador. But, again, I do not claim to be absolutely certain about those propositions in the sense that it would be impossible that I should be mistaken about them. However, what I do claim is that I am not mistaken about them, and that my justification for them is sufficient for me to claim that I know them.
I don't have to know "all there is to know about Quito" in order to know that Quito is the capital of Ecuador. Indeed, I really have no idea what it would even mean "to know all about Quito" and I suggest that you do not know what that means either. Why do you think that knowing that Quito is a meaningless bit of information? I can't think why you say that. In any case, I don't claim to know what is meaningful (whatever that might be) but I do claim to know many things such as those three propositions I have just listed. (But I think that, for instance, I know that many people were killed in World War 2, and I don't think that anyone believes that is a "meaningless bit of information")
If by "truth is not always true" you mean that true statement are not always true, I am afraid that is a contradiction. True statements are true is a necessary truth. I cannot imagine what you can literally mean when you say that true statements are not always true. That sounds like a bit of poetry to me. It is true that sometimes (I hope not often) we may have (in order to have a "relationship") lie to others. But that unfortunate necessity, (if it exists) surely does not show that true statement are not always true. What it shows is that sometimes we may have to lie and tell others that what is true is not true. I am not sure that I would want to have a "relationship" that required a lie to maintain it.
How do you recognize objects you don't know? At some point everyone has to say: yes this is the thing I know. In my short spell in the university I had an ATL professor who talked about two men on a train seeing a herd of brown cows. Th first said: Look at the beautiful herd of brown cows! The Second man said: They are only brown on this side.
It is possible that we cannot know anything we cannot see both sides of, but knowledge is also a function of intuition, imagination, and recollection. All of these at once present a picture, or idea in our minds when we recognize something new as something known. Knowledge is judgement, and if you can judge, and not just speak the truth regarding a, or any finite object then you know it. What we do is in regard to reality even if the tool we use to know is the concept. If the concept were not true to reality we could not change reality, and that is something humanity has been doing for a long time. If the question is: Whether our knowledge will ever be complete, so that knowledge means that we know all? The answer is that the knife of investigation can always skin off another layer of reality to reveal the meat beneith. One generation says they know the tree is green, and the next says why the tree is green and each is as justified in saying they know what they know.
You have already told me almost all I can say I know about Quito, and since I have it on faith I don't count on it for much. No judgement stands in issolation. No one learns a fact about physics, but learns physics as a scientific discipline. Even systems of belief pretenting to be knowledge stand together for support. I have never, personally learned anything of value as a fact. My education is incomplete. My formal education is minimal. I have only been able to learn by putting every fact as much in relation to every other as possible. If I say I know a little of everything it might sound like I know a lot of nothing. What I think I know is what people know, which is to say, I think I know where human knowledge stands at this moment, and I know what people used to think they knew, and howthey thought they knew, and what has changed to the present. If I am a polymath I am an uneducated one. Knowledge for me is not one specific fact, but knowing how each particular fact relates, which is meaning, as meaning is value. In the example beginning this discussion regarding the penny, if one does not know how the penny relates, and what the penny means, or has no sense of the knowledge of metalurgy involved in its minting, or the economy to which it belongs, its value in relation to other currency; then one does not know enough. Knowledge is not issolated knowledge, but something complete. Knowledge is judgement which involves many aspects of an object, but is not just about the object, but is about all objects. It is as important to ask how do we learn, as how do we know, since beginning with so much hearsay, and suppositions is not very auspicious unless one is blessed witha curious and critical mind.
If by "truth is not always true" you mean that true statement are not always true, I am afraid that is a contradiction. True statements are true is a necessary truth. I cannot imagine what you can literally mean when you say that true statements are not always true. That sounds like a bit of poetry to me. It is true that sometimes (I hope not often) we may have (in order to have a "relationship") lie to others. But that unfortunate necessity, (if it exists) surely does not show that true statement are not always true. What it shows is that sometimes we may have to lie and tell others that what is true is not true. I am not sure that I would want to have a "relationship" that required a lie to maintain it.
kennethamy wrote:The truth is not always true means that truth is a form of relationship as well as a perfect ideal representation of reality. Truth is a social and emotional phenomenon. Everybody feels true just as they feel real, but very often people harbor great contradictions within their lives, their selves. If you challenge what a person accepts as true you are challenging the person in their emotional home, their soul, if you will. I would consider myself both happy and wise if I could keep all contradictions external to myself.
I pity the poor philosophers, and sceptics, and scientists that dared to tell the truth and died on a pile of cinders. They gave up the only important thing, life, to give to people a non thing, truth, when those people could not give that non thing truth a value. I think I would rather have the truth and have my life than have nothing. Truth is only a form. The relationship is essential to our lives even if truth might be essential to the improvement of our lives. I would not tell you to lie. I might tell you to hint at the truth if the truth were something to enrage the population. Just as people look at themselves as true, each should look at the truth as a personal and prized possession. There are only certain people you can share with. If we are coy with the truth then time will tell it for us. If one people disregards the truth another will displace them with the truth. Can you say one does not know when knowledge makes every army victorious?
In terms of human relationship the truth is a fast fish, or a ginger bread man. If you got it fine. It belongs for the moment to the one who owns it, but tomorrow a new truth will supplant your truth, and the treasure you hold so tightly will be sand.
In the example beginning this discussion regarding the penny, if one does not know how the penny relates, and what the penny means, or has no sense of the knowledge of metalurgy involved in its minting, or the economy to which it belongs, its value in relation to other currency; then one does not know enough.
I know enough to know that a penny is a coin, for instance. And that in U.S. currency it is worth 1/100th of a dollar. I know many things about pennies. And so do you. But I do not have to know everything there is to know about a penny (and I have no idea what that would be, and neither do you) in order to know quite a few things about pennies. In fact, I don't have to know everything there is to know about anything (if, indeed, the phrase, "Everything known about X" has any clear meaning) in order to know many things about it. What we can claim to know is limited by context. In most contexts we confine what we can be said to know about something to what, in that context, it is important to know. For instance, I do not have to know anything about metallurgy, in order to know a great deal about pennies in the context of what a penny is worth.
Your views about what knowledge is, are confused with a certain picture you seem to have about what knowledge should be. You think that unless one knows all, one cannot know some (or at least the "some" is insignificant) But that would imply that no one could know something, since, it is clear that no one can know everything. But that no one can know something is false. So the view that no one can know unless he knows everything must be false. Another part of the picture you seem to have about knowledge is that unless one is absolutely certain (where that means, "cannot be mistaken") one does not know at all. But that also seems to be false. For I know that, for instance, Quito is the capital of Ecuador, but although I am not mistaken about that, I can see how I might be mistaken about that. (The confusion is between the truth that if I know, I am not mistaken, with the falsity that if I know, I cannot be mistaken).
What is ideal is one thing, what is real is another thing. (Although Plato confused the two). And the rejection of the real because it is not ideal is an ancient philosophical error, which is not less an error for being ancient.
kennethamy wrote:If you knew only one thing you would know nothing. Knowledge is judgement, and to judge one must have other knowledge to judge by. To say some true thing about some strange object is meaningless unless you, with knowledge, are talking to me as some one with knowledge as well; in particular: The meaning of words. You say: The table top is hard and flat. What is hard and flat? Where is the meaning if not ultimately in sense and experience, then in judgement, and then in the ability to communicate the judgement in forms of meaning. Knowledge, like a truth, is a form of relationship, not only between external reality and external reality, but between external reality and conceptual, internal reality; and then between people who relate through the forms of knowledge and experience.
If you knew only one thing you would know nothing.
But that is an obvious contradiction. If you knew only one thing, you would not know nothing, you would know that one thing. You cannot both know nothing, and know one thing.
It may be that I have to know other things to know something, but that means only, that if I know something I know other things, not that if I know only one thing, then I know nothing.
You just toss about the term "meaningless" as if it was clear what it means. You probably mean by "meaningless" insignificant, or unimportant, but not "incomprehensible".If I know only that Bigfoot is a large creature, and nothing else about Bigfoot, I do know something. Perhaps not in your opinion significant, but still I know something about Bigfoot.
I am sorry, but I do not know what "conceptual internal reality" is. I agree that for me to know that the table is brown, I must have the concepts of table and brown, but so what? I can still know that the table is brown without knowing anything else.
I would like to add here for the benefit of visitors a portion of text from the Wiki entry on Transcendental Idealism:
Transcendental idealism is a doctrine founded by 18th-century German philosopher Immanuel Kant. Kant presents it as the point of view which holds that our experience of things is about how they appear to us, not about those things as they are in and of themselves.
[CENTER]. . .[/CENTER]
Perhaps the best way to approach transcendental idealism is by looking at Kant's account of how we intuit (Ge: anschauen) objects. What's relevant here is that space and time, rather than being real things-in-themselves or empirically mediated appearances (Ge: Erscheinungen), are the very forms of intuition (Ge: Anschauung) by which we must perceive objects. They are hence neither to be considered properties that we may attribute to objects in perceiving them, nor substantial entities of themselves. They are in that sense subjective, yet necessary preconditions of any given object insofar as this object is an appearance and not a thing-in-itself. Humans necessarily perceive objects spatially and temporally. This is part of what it means for a human to cognize an object, to perceive it as something both spatial and temporal. These are all claims Kant argues for in the section of the Critique of Pure Reason entitled the Transcendental Aesthetic. This section is devoted to the inquiry of the a priori conditions of (human) sensibility, i.e. the faculty by which objects are apprehended.
[CENTER]. . .[/CENTER]
Kant succinctly defined transcendental idealism in this way:[INDENT][E]verything intuited or perceived in space and time, and therefore all objects of a possible experience, are nothing but phenomenal appearances, that is, mere representations, which in the way in which they are represented to us, as extended beings, or as series of changes, have no independent, self-subsistent existence apart from our thoughts.[/INDENT][INDENT]- Critique of Pure Reason, A491[/INDENT]
With regard to the adjective "transcendental" itself, Kant defined it in the following way when he used it to describe knowledge:[INDENT]"I call all knowledge transcendental if it is occupied, not with objects, but with the way that we can possibly know objects, even before we experience them."[/INDENT][INDENT]- Critique of Pure Reason, A12[/INDENT]And In the first edition of the Critique, Kant stated:
"However exaggerated and absurd it may sound, to say that the understanding is itself the source of the laws of nature, . . . such an assertion is none the less correct." (Transcendental Deduction, Section 3).
I would like to add here for the benefit of visitors a portion of text from the Wiki entry on Transcendental Idealism:
Transcendental idealism is a doctrine founded by 18th-century German philosopher Immanuel Kant. Kant presents it as the point of view which holds that our experience of things is about how they appear to us, not about those things as they are in and of themselves.
[CENTER]. . .[/CENTER]
I like the way Kant explains things; but I must disagree. First with this last statement, since nature has its own logic and what we call logical only follows nature.
And third: that space and time are subjective since we occupy space, and are time. We live, we are life which is a special form of matter that exists in time, and manipulates matter in space. Normally these quasi concepts only give subjective context to reality, but to people they are the only objective reality.
Look up what Kant says of transendental imagination. If I understand his point, it is how we recognize phenomenon as fitting into a catagory without having the whole finite object in our hands. We cannot possibly see things whole; or their whole nature. We sense a part that stands for the whole, and with imagination and a portion of the object we transend to a sense of the whole. This is the quality that allows our reference to God or existence as real concepts, as wholes when they are infinites.