numbers vs. words

Get Email Updates Email this Topic Print this Page

Ahab
 
Reply Mon 5 Apr, 2010 08:13 pm
@Extrain,
Extrain;148373 wrote:




[quote=Ahab]There doesn't seem to me to be anything awry with the expression "The tiger is fierce". If, the context of where it is used there is uncertainty over what the speaker is trying to say with that expression, then we simply have to ask them.
[/COLOR]
I am inclined to agree. and?... [/QUOTE]
And:
Ahab: Which tiger do you believe is so fierce?
Speaker: I wasn't using 'the tiger' to refer to a tiger.
Ahab: Don't you know that 'the tiger' in the sentence you uttered is to be used to refer to something?
Speaker: Oh, yes. I know that is how it is supposed to be used.
Ahab: Then you used it to refer to something else?
Speaker: No. Actually I wasn't using it to refer to anything else.
Ahab: Then how were you using it?
Speaker: I was just uttering it.
All I can conclude is that the speaker did not intend to say anything meaningful by uttering the sentence he did.
I can't accuse him of breaking any grammatical rules. That would be like accusing someone who wasn't engaged in a game of chess of breaking a rule because they were playing around with moving chess pieces randomly across a chessboard.
Looking back at the start of this discussion, I am aware that you brought up this sentence in order to illustrate the importance of context in determining how a sentence is used. I think you made that point very well.
It is still not clear to me why you think this scenario also illustrates a violation of the rules of language use. If there is not context to help determine the meaning expressed by the use of a sentence, then all that is left is the meaning of the sentence. Do you think the sentence doesn't have a meaning? I think it has a meaning.

[quote]He's supposed to be using "the tiger" as a referring term to express a proposition for which he failed to express.[/quote]
But I don't think he is even trying to express a proposition, as I've indicated above.

Quote:

Just as in the "If you can read this, then you are not using public transportation like you should be."

But in this instance we do have a context which helps us to understand how the sentence is being used: it is part of an advertisement campaign. Advertisers are not concerned about the truth, they want to sell a product. In this instance the product is public transportation.

[quote]Take the bus example. Are not someone's intentions immediately given by their failure to refer to the appropriate individual(s) by his use of the indexical "you"? This is the same thing. Even if he his overall intention is to create a catcy slogan, he is also intending to say something truth-valuable which he failed to do. Are you telliing me you don't understand this?? It's obvious to me.[/quote]
What is obvious to me is that what advertisers want is to sell a product. If the sentence leads to an increased use in public transportation then it has served that intent very well.
It seems clear to me that the language used in a religious ritual is going to differ from language used in advertisements or language used in a scientific journal.
There are many different kinds of propositions: empirical, legal, logical, mathematical, religious, etc.
Do your tools of analysis take into account these differences?
 
Extrain
 
Reply Mon 5 Apr, 2010 09:22 pm
@Ahab,
Ahab;148713 wrote:
And:
Ahab: Which tiger do you believe is so fierce?
Speaker: I wasn't using 'the tiger' to refer to a tiger.
Ahab: Don't you know that 'the tiger' in the sentence you uttered is to be used to refer to something?
Speaker: Oh, yes. I know that is how it is supposed to be used.
Ahab: Then you used it to refer to something else?
Speaker: No. Actually I wasn't using it to refer to anything else.
Ahab: Then how were you using it?
Speaker: I was just uttering it.
All I can conclude is that the speaker did not intend to say anything meaningful by uttering the sentence he did.


But he wasn't just "uttering it," or "mentioning it." Mentioning a sentence is way different than using it to try to ASSERT something. He was intending to say something truth-valuable by uttering it, knowing the referring term he is using fails to pick anything out. So his intentions are inconsistent with how the term "the tiger" is actually used in everyday discourse. That's how I understand that context.

Ahab;148713 wrote:
What is being violated is the need to be using one's is that people should be using their language in a coherent way when they intend to express something. I can't accuse him of breaking any grammatical rules. That would be like accusing someone who wasn't engaged in a game of chess of breaking a rule because they were playing around with moving chess pieces randomly across a chessboard.


Right, and in my last post, I surrendered this point to you. You take rules of language to be grammatico-syntactical rules. Strictly speaking, I think that's right. I went ahead and said that no grammatical or syntactical rules are being violated at all, in this case. Rather, someone is failing to be using his language sensibly, intelligently, or wisely. When people make declarative statements about the world such as "abortion is wrong," they intend to say something, not only meaningful, but also truth-valuable. That "something" is the proposition that gets expressed in declarative utterances. But if you know that the referring term in the sentence you are using fails to pick anything out, then you are not using your language sensibly or intelligently, and you fail to express a proposition. Someone is just being dumb.

[QUOTE=Ahab;148713]Do you think the sentence doesn't have a meaning? I think it has a meaning.[/QUOTE]

I don't think "Hamlet exists" has any meaning. Do contradictions have meaning? hmmm...

[QUOTE=Ahab;148713] But I don't think he is even trying to express a proposition, as I've indicated above.[/QUOTE]

But that's not how I set it up the example. Look, I hear people all the time trying to make statements they think have a truth-value, but are really not.

E.g., "Being is not nothing," or "Unicorns exist as an idea," or "Hamlet exists," or "Time is subjective." Statements like these are not truthvaluable. They don't pick anything out. These statements either assert what they deny exists (which is a contradiction), or the person simply doesn't know what he or she is trying to say. And it's an irresponsible way of making use of language.

[QUOTE=Ahab;148713] But in this instance we do have a context which helps us to understand how the sentence is being used: it is part of an advertisement campaign. Advertisers are not concerned about the truth, they want to sell a product. In this instance the product is public transportation.
What is obvious to me is that what advertisers want is to sell a product.[/QUOTE]


...which is precisely why I think advertisements screw up the sensible use of language...and I don't respect advertisements at all in many cases--especially those which abuse language--or speak illogically.

[QUOTE=Ahab;148713] It seems clear to me that the language used in a religious ritual is going to differ from language used in advertisements or language used in a scientific journal.[/QUOTE]
Ahab;148713 wrote:

There are many different kinds of propositions: empirical, legal, logical, mathematical, religious, etc.
Do your tools of analysis take into account these differences?


Of course, these are all different contextual uses of language. But if someone is not using his or her language intelligently at all, then he or she is not using his or her language like it ought to be used.
 
Ahab
 
Reply Tue 6 Apr, 2010 07:42 am
@Extrain,
Extrain;148722 wrote:
But he wasn't just "uttering it," or "mentioning it." Mentioning a sentence is way different than using it to try to ASSERT something. He was intending to say something truth-valuable by uttering it, knowing the referring term he is using fails to pick anything out. So his intentions are inconsistent with how the term "the tiger" is actually used in everyday discourse. That's how I understand that context.



Right, and in my last post, I surrendered this point to you. You take rules of language to be grammatico-syntactical rules. Strictly speaking, I think that's right. I went ahead and said that no grammatical or syntactical rules are being violated at all, in this case. Rather, someone is failing to be using his language sensibly, intelligently, or wisely. When people make declarative statements about the world such as "abortion is wrong," they intend to say something, not only meaningful, but also truth-valuable. That "something" is the proposition that gets expressed in declarative utterances. But if you know that the referring term in the sentence you are using fails to pick anything out, then you are not using your language sensibly or intelligently, and you fail to express a proposition. Someone is just being dumb.



I don't think "Hamlet exists" has any meaning. Do contradictions have meaning? hmmm...



But that's not how I set it up the example. Look, I hear people all the time trying to make statements they think have a truth-value, but are really not.

E.g., "Being is not nothing," or "Unicorns exist as an idea," or "Hamlet exists," or "Time is subjective." Statements like these are not truthvaluable. They don't pick anything out. These statements either assert what they deny exists (which is a contradiction), or the person simply doesn't know what he or she is trying to say. And it's an irresponsible way of making use of language.



...which is precisely why I think advertisements screw up the sensible use of language...and I don't respect advertisements at all in many cases--especially those which abuse language--or speak illogically.



Of course, these are all different contextual uses of language. But if someone is not using his or her language intelligently at all, then he or she is not using his or her language like it ought to be used.



Gee, if this is what you were trying to say, why didn't you use a sentence like "It is 3 pm on the sun"? or 'rocks have experiences'?

The sentence "The tiger is fierce' is perfectly fine. It doesn't violate any logico-grammatical rules. And, as the kung fu example illustrated, someone could assert it meaningfully if 'the tiger' referred to a particular move in kung fu.

---------- Post added 04-06-2010 at 08:17 AM ----------

Extrain;148722 wrote:

But that's not how I set it up the example. Look, I hear people all the time trying to make statements they think have a truth-value, but are really not.

E.g., "Being is not nothing," or "Unicorns exist as an idea," or "Hamlet exists," or "Time is subjective." Statements like these are not truthvaluable. They don't pick anything out. These statements either assert what they deny exists (which is a contradiction), or the person simply doesn't know what he or she is trying to say. And it's an irresponsible way of making use of language.



I hope you don't hold the position that language essentially is used to make assertions about the world we live in. That we should analyze all sentences as if they were assertions.

There are many uses for words and sentences.
 
Extrain
 
Reply Tue 6 Apr, 2010 12:33 pm
@Ahab,
Ahab;148780 wrote:
Gee, if this is what you were trying to say, why didn't you use a sentence like "It is 3 pm on the sun"? or 'rocks have experiences'?

The sentence "The tiger is fierce' is perfectly fine. It doesn't violate any logico-grammatical rules. And, as the kung fu example illustrated, someone could assert it meaningfully if 'the tiger' referred to a particular move in kung fu.


If the student meant "the kung fu move of the tiger is fierce," that would be fine. Anything else is very problematic.

So don't you think there are rules concerning how we should and should not be using language? I mentioned in the beginning the kind of rules I was talking about were analogous to "moral" rules...remember? I never said they were syntactic/grammatical rules anyway. But I just now realized that's exactly what you were talking about.

I think both of us were being a little "thick in the head."

In any grammar and composition class in high school, you get to take apart the structure of sentences...subject, predicate, DO, IO, prepositional phrases, nominal complements, etc, etc,--and catalogue which part is doint what, and how it is functioning with respect to the rest of the sentence....

These rules, however, don't tell you if "untrained green ideas sleep furiously" is meaningless or not. You need other rules...what are those rules? Are they semantic rules? contextual rules? Rules of discourse? I think so, actually!

Grice, Searle, Strawson, Davidson....are all phil's of language who discuss these other rules of discourse in various essays...

Ahab;148780 wrote:
I hope you don't hold the position that language essentially is used to make assertions about the world we live in. That we should analyze all sentences as if they were assertions.

There are many uses for words and sentences.


Of course, no one would make exclamations, make promises, command others to do things, etc., if there weren't.

I think you are having the similar trouble that mickalos was having--that just because I was analyzing the sentence of an advertizement on the back of a bus, that somehow I was not able to recognize these different purposes of language use. But which purpose you have in conveying an implied message is an altogether different question whether or not the sentenced used to convey that message is intelligible or not. In the case of the bus, it is not. Call me "meticulously one-sided," it doesn't matter. Philosophers do this all the time.

You know how when students take an exam, a professor will often silently put *the time* on the chalk board in order to tell students how much time remaining they have left on their exam?

I remember as an undergraduate this scenario:

5 minutes before class started when all the students were finding their seats, our professor began erasing the chalk on the chalk board made from the previous class. Apparently, the students from the prior class had an exam, because my professor erased a chalk time-indication that said "Time:12:45." But as he erased it, he mumbled to himself "I am erasing this falsehood,"--and he was right. The time indicated was false. But everyone thought it was funny. You probably don't want to be good friends with a guy like that, because he is weird after all, but that doesn't mean he wasn't correct.

Philosophers are sometimes like that, I guess....
 
Ahab
 
Reply Wed 7 Apr, 2010 06:48 pm
@Extrain,
Extrain;148852 wrote:

Ahab wrote:

Gee, if this is what you were trying to say, why didn't you use a sentence like "It is 3 pm on the sun"? or 'rocks have experiences'?

The sentence "The tiger is fierce' is perfectly fine. It doesn't violate any logico-grammatical rules. And, as the kung fu example illustrated, someone could assert it meaningfully if 'the tiger' referred to a particular move in kung fu.


If the student meant "the kung fu move of the tiger is fierce," that would be fine. Anything else is very problematic.

I don't see why. Certainly I can see situations in which it would be problematical to use the sentence 'the tiger is fierce'. But that doesn't mean there is a real problem with this particular sentence. Any sentence can be misused.

Quote:

So don't you think there are rules concerning how we should and should not be using language? I mentioned in the beginning the kind of rules I was talking about were analogous to "moral" rules...remember? I never said they were syntactic/grammatical rules anyway. But I just now realized that's exactly what you were talking about.

That is not exactly what I was talking about. I'm not limiting myself to syntax. Rather I'm extending the use of 'grammar' to refer to any sense- or meaning-determining rules for the use of words. Sorry, I didn't make that clear from the beginning.

I think language is a public, rule governed practice. It is partly constitutive of the form of life and culture of its speakers.
The meaning of a word is what is given by an explanation of meaning and an explanation of meaning is a rule for the use of the word explained, a standard of correct use.


Quote:
I think both of us were being a little "thick in the head."


I can't argue with that. :bigsmile:



Quote:
Ahab wrote:

I hope you don't hold the position that language essentially is used to make assertions about the world we live in. That we should analyze all sentences as if they were assertions.

There are many uses for words and sentences.


Of course, no one would make exclamations, make promises, command others to do things, etc., if there weren't.

I think you are having the similar trouble that mickalos was having--that just because I was analyzing the sentence of an advertisement on the back of a bus, that somehow I was not able to recognize these different purposes of language use. But which purpose you have in conveying an implied message is an altogether different question whether or not the sentenced used to convey that message is intelligible or not. In the case of the bus, it is not. Call me "meticulously one-sided," it doesn't matter. Philosophers do this all the time.


"If you can read this, then you are not using public transportation like you should be."

The meaning of the sentence appears to me to be quite intelligible.
Are you saying that you really don't understand the meaning of the sentence? I'm not talking about how it is being used but merely what it means.
I see no violation of grammatical rules as in this sentence : "It is 3 p.m. on the sun." I don't know what that sentence means, do you?

Quote:

You know how when students take an exam, a professor will often silently put *the time* on the chalk board in order to tell students how much time remaining they have left on their exam?

I remember as an undergraduate this scenario:

5 minutes before class started when all the students were finding their seats, our professor began erasing the chalk on the chalk board made from the previous class. Apparently, the students from the prior class had an exam, because my professor erased a chalk time-indication that said "Time:12:45." But as he erased it, he mumbled to himself "I am erasing this falsehood,"--and he was right. The time indicated was false. But everyone thought it was funny. You probably don't want to be good friends with a guy like that, because he is weird after all, but that doesn't mean he wasn't correct.

That is pretty funny.:bigsmile:

But why do you think he was correct? I think what he expressed by his mumbling is a wrongheaded view of language. I hope he didn't teach philosophy.:eek:
The meaning of a sentence or expression is not true or false. What is said by the use of the sentence can be true or false. Why would one think that what was expressed by the use of 'Time:12:45' : you only have until 12:45 to complete the test, was a falsehood?
 
Extrain
 
Reply Wed 7 Apr, 2010 07:51 pm
@Ahab,
Ahab;149447 wrote:
I don't see why. Certainly I can see situations in which it would be problematical to use the sentence 'the tiger is fierce'. But that doesn't mean there is a real problem with this particular sentence. Any sentence can be misused.


Yes!

Ahab;149447 wrote:
That is not exactly what I was talking about. I'm not limiting myself to syntax. Rather I'm extending the use of 'grammar' to refer to any sense- or meaning-determining rules for the use of words. Sorry, I didn't make that clear from the beginning.

I think language is a public, rule governed practice. It is partly constitutive of the form of life and culture of its speakers.
The meaning of a word is what is given by an explanation of meaning and an explanation of meaning is a rule for the use of the word explained, a standard of correct use.


...then where, exactly, is our disagreement???

Ahab;149447 wrote:
"If you can read this, then you are not using public transportation like you should be."

The meaning of the sentence appears to me to be quite intelligible.
Are you saying that you really don't understand the meaning of the sentence? I'm not talking about how it is being used but merely what it means.


No, that's not what I am saying. I am saying (like I've said many times now) that I can't determine what proposition the sentence literally expresses, even though I can easily gather what the author intended to express. We come to know what that implied proposition is, namely that, "all car-drivers should be using public transportation," but the sentence itself doesn't express this proposition because it flouts the proper use of the meaning (or semantic content) of "you." The rule of use for "you" is: the function that maps the speaker to the person (or the value of the indexical "you") in a given context of discourse. The problem is that there is no speaker, hence there is no "speaker context." So, the context has to be filled in by our knowledge of background conditions, such as our knowledge of the fact that that sentence occured on a bus.

Notice, if that sentence was found on a piece of paper lying on the ground, you wouldn't know to which class of people designated by "you" that sentence referred. It would be indeterminate, and so you wouldn't know which proposition got expressed by that sentence! So context is important.

The point with the bus example is that there exists a huge gap between the assertoric content of the utterance of the sentence-type of this kind (what is expressed in ordinary utterances of this type of sentence) and the semantic contents of this sentence (what this sentence literally expresses, in the contexts of utterance [for which there is no context at all--not the kind provided by the indexical "you," anyway]).

So the context has to filled in by us. That context is the description "all and only those who drive cars and can read this sign."

Ahab;149447 wrote:
I see no violation of grammatical rules as in this sentence : "It is 3 p.m. on the sun." I don't know what that sentence means, do you?


That depends on your view of time. If Special Theory of Relativity is true, then that sentence doesn't make any sense.

(I, however, don't think STR is true--I know, big scientific heresy on my part.)

Ahab;149447 wrote:
But why do you think he was correct? I think what he expressed by his mumbling is a wrongheaded view of language. I hope he didn't teach philosophy.:eek:The meaning of a sentence or expression is not true or false. What is said by the use of the sentence can be true or false.


you're just being uncharitable...the guy is well-published, and knows his philosophy.

That's what he meant: "the proposition expressed by this sentence is false."

Ahab;149447 wrote:
Why would one think that what was expressed by the use of 'Time:12:45' : you only have until 12:45 to complete the test, was a falsehood?


That's not even what was expressed by that sentence.

What was expressed was: <the time is now 12:45>.

And that IS false, if the time is now 12:55.
 
Ahab
 
Reply Thu 8 Apr, 2010 07:08 am
@Extrain,
Extrain;149459 wrote:

...then where, exactly, is our disagreement???


It appears to me that despite your acknowledged recognition of language being used in many different way, you want to treat every sentence you analyse as if it were an assertion.
The sentence on the back of the bus is not being used to express a belief that drivers should ride in buses. It presupposes that belief.


Quote:

Ahab wrote:

I see no violation of grammatical rules as in this sentence : "It is 3 p.m. on the sun." I don't know what that sentence means, do you?


That depends on your view of time. If Special Theory of Relativity is true, then that sentence doesn't make any sense.


No it doesn't depend on my view of time. It depends on what rules have been given for the use of the words in that sentence. Those rules are set by convention. No scientific theory is going to give that sentence a meaning. The only way it can have a meaning is if we change the rules for the use of '3 p.m'.

And what I intended to say by that sentence is irrelevant to determining its meaning. And whether it is true or not is irrelevant to determining its meaning.


Quote:

That's not even what was expressed by that sentence.

What was expressed was: <the time is now 12:45>.

And that IS false, if the time is now 12:55.


Did I misunderstand what you were saying? I thought the professor would write down the time that the test would end in order that the students would know how much time they had left.:perplexed:
 
kennethamy
 
Reply Thu 8 Apr, 2010 07:18 am
@Extrain,
Extrain;149459 wrote:
Yes!

No, that's not what I am saying. I am saying (like I've said many times now) that I can't determine what proposition the sentence literally expresses, even though I can easily gather what the author intended to express. We come to know what that implied proposition is, namely that, "all car-drivers should be using public transportation," but the sentence itself doesn't express this proposition because it flouts the proper use of the meaning (or semantic content) of "you." The rule of use for "you" is: the function that maps the speaker to the person (or the value of the indexical "you") in a given context of discourse. The problem is that there is no speaker, hence there is no "speaker context." So, the context has to be filled in by our knowledge of background conditions, such as our knowledge of the fact that that sentence occured on a bus.


.


I am jumping into this late, but isn't the speaker who ever it is that runs the bus company, and the audience who ever is reading the notice (presumably also riding the bus)? Isn't is exactly like a memo, or a letter beginning with, "To whom it may concern"?
 
Extrain
 
Reply Thu 8 Apr, 2010 07:02 pm
@kennethamy,
kennethamy;149566 wrote:
I am jumping into this late, but isn't the speaker who ever it is that runs the bus company, and the audience who ever is reading the notice (presumably also riding the bus)? Isn't is exactly like a memo, or a letter beginning with, "To whom it may concern"?


Yes, but none of those bare facts alone present any problems that I can see.

I am just unravelling the semantic parts of sentences and trying to determine whether these semantic parts contribute to what gets literally expressed and which semantic parts don't contribute directly to what gets literally expressed. Many times what the speaker meant to say doesn't always match up with what he literally did say. I think this is pretty clear.

"To whom it may concern" already provides the context within the written salutation itself. The rule of use for "whom" is "a function mapping the writer (speaker) to a person in any context within which the writer (speaker) and that person are a part." The context, here, is "any of those who would be concerned about 'it', which in turn refers to 'what is going to be said in this memo.'"

Though the rule of use for "you" in the bus example is very similar just because of what "you" means, the context for "you" in this example, on the other hand, is not immediately given by what is literally expressed by that sentence at all, unlike the context immediately given in the written memo itself. In the bus example, we have to infer this context (which is "all and only those persons who drive cars") from our own implicit knowledge of backgound conditions, most notably from our own knowledge of the fact that the very sentence occurs on the back of a bus. If that sentence did not occur on the back of a bus but were encountered on a piece of paper we randomly chanced to find lying on the ground somewhere in a supermarket instead, we could not determine to whom "you" was referring--therefore, what proposition got expressed by that sentence on the back of the bus is impossible for us to determine from the "written word" itself actually located on the back of the bus. (It's a "pain in the butt" trying to figure out what is really going on here in the bus example!)

The memo is different: the context for "whom" is directly given by the very salutation itself "...anyone who would be concerned about what this memo ('it') is about to say."

---------- Post added 04-08-2010 at 08:17 PM ----------

Ahab;149563 wrote:
It appears to me that despite your acknowledged recognition of language being used in many different way, you want to treat every sentence you analyse as if it were an assertion.


But most sentences are assertions.

"[You] Go get me a beer..." is not an assertion, and maybe it is a sentence--though it is definitely a command.

"I promise to mary you" is not an assertion, though it is a sentence--and it is a speech-act.

"I hereby name this ship, 'The Titanic'" is not an assertion, though it is a sentence--and it is a speech-act.

"Ouch!" is not an assertion, nor is it a sentence--it is an exclamation.

Ahab;149563 wrote:
The sentence on the back of the bus is not being used to express a belief that drivers should ride in buses. It presupposes that belief.


huh? The sentence on the bus does all of the above. Something is said--so what is that "thing" that is said? What is said can either be true or false--and if "that something" is true or false, then it is something obviously (though ambiguously) stated. And if "that something" is stated, then there is a proposition embedded in that statement. The proposition is just buried underneath all the humor--but it is definitely there.

(1) The sentence presupposes 2 beliefs: (a) that all drivers should be riding buses--which is a normative belief.
(2) The sentence is also being used to express the content of the author's other belief (b) that "All those regularly driving cars are not using public transportation like they should be"--the content of this belief is factual, not normative.
(3) The sentence also literally says,

(a) "If you can read this, then you are not using public transportation like you should be."

That is an assertion, and the author clearly meant to say something by choosing those words that he did to put on the back of the bus. So the proposition intended to be expressed by the author is,

(b) <All those who regularly drive cars are not using public transportation like they should be>

But what is literally expressed (a) does not match up with the proposition he intended to express (b), nor is there any literally implied sentence meaning to mediate between (a) and (b) either such as,

(c) "If you can read this and are driving a car, then you are not using public transportation like you should be.'

because it is not clear what context is giving "you" the appropriate reference in the sentence (a). So the author is misusing "you" to convey the proposition (b) without any mediation of any implied sentence meaning (c). So the sentence (a) neither literally expresses nor literally implies the proposition (b)--even though we can all infer which proposition, namely (b), the author intended to express from our own implicit background knowledge of what the author most likely would have meant by (a), such that he probably meant (c), and from our own contextual knowledge that the sentence (a) occurred on the back of a bus.

So, the proposition that the author wants to express (b) does not actually get expressed by the sentence (a), but ironically enough, this "cheated success" in conveying (b) is only accomplished by his very misuse of the very indexical pronoun "you"--(and so this is why his humour becomes somewhat of a funny joke--but these kinds of things will drive a philosopher mad, like myself. Call me "friggin bored").

(4) The author's overall purpose of putting that sentence on the back of the bus is to get automobile drivers to stop driving as much as they do, and to start using public transportation--but this overall purpose has nothing to do with the actual sentences or propositions at hand.

Ahab;149563 wrote:
No it doesn't depend on my view of time. It depends on what rules have been given for the use of the words in that sentence. Those rules are set by convention. No scientific theory is going to give that sentence a meaning. The only way it can have a meaning is if we change the rules for the use of '3 p.m'.


Actually, what that sentence means does depend on your own view of time, since people mean different things by "time."

So can you tell me which "semantic" or "conventional" rules are being violated here by saying "It is 3pm on the sun right now?" Is it because "3pm" is an expression that only has meaning with respect to earth time and no time anywhere else?...I'm not sure I've figured out what is going on here yet.

Ahab;149563 wrote:
And what I intended to say by that sentence is irrelevant to determining its meaning. And whether it is true or not is irrelevant to determining its meaning.


True, the meanings of words of the parts of sentences and the speaker's intentions by using those sentence come apart. And it is also true that, whether or not the proposition expressed by that sentence is true is not dependent on whether Bill or Bob determines its meaning in fact. But it is also true that you couldn't determine which proposition gets expressed by that sentence (assuming there is any proposition at all expressed by the literal meanings of the parts of the sentence) without also actually determining the meanings of the words in that sentence.

Which propositions get expressed by sentences are a direct function of the meanings of parts of sentences. Why would anyone deny this?

There are two consequences of this:

(1) no one can determine which proposition gets expressed by a sentence if that sentence is ambiguous or fails to be clear.
(2) No proposition, in fact, gets literally expressed by that sentence if the literal meanings of the parts of that sentence do not functionally map to any determinate unambiguous parts of a proposition.

But often, we do

(3) "Fill in" the semantic values of the proposition the speaker intended to express by his choice of words.--This is the implied meaning that we induce apart from the literal semantic values of the sentence itself. So these semantic values which occur in the intended proposition are not always actually contained in the sentence itself--but are "filled in" by us later.

Ahab;149563 wrote:
Did I misunderstand what you were saying? I thought the professor would write down the time that the test would end in order that the students would know how much time they had left.:perplexed:


That's why he wrote that sentence down, so that the students would know how much time they had left on the test. But that's not what the sentence says, nor is that what the sentence implies--but none of that is problematic.

"Time: 12:45" is what is literally said.
"The time is now 12:45pm" is what is literally implied.
And,
<The time is now 12:45> is the proposition that is literally implied to be true by the teacher by what he literally says or writes, namely, "Time:12:45."

And this proposition is false 1 or 2 minutes later (assuming alot of controversial things about time-indexes as being a part of the structure of propositions themselves--which is a whole different matter. Most philosophers that I know actually think propositions, once true, are always true since "past, present, and future tenses" are all indexed to to "now"...)

But that the student now has 5 minutes left to finish his or her test is neither what is implied, nor what is literally said. This is just a further fact the student can deduce for himself or herself from his or her own knowledge that class ends at 12:50pm.

Don't we have to at least start making distinctions between some of these following items (and perhaps more)?

(1) Literal Sentence meaning--which is a function of the syntactical/grammatical meaning-units of the parts of a sentence. E.g., "Time: 12:45"
(2) Literal Sentence-Implied meaning--which is a function of (1) and our own background knowledge of HOW these syntactical/grammatical meaning-units are TYPICALLY combined by other people in our language to yield a completed sentence-meaning-picture independent of outside context altogether. E.g., "Time is 12:45pm."
(3) Literal contextual sentence meaning--which is a function of (1), (2), and our knowing the actual contextual variables in place within the context the sentence is actually uttered or written--which is what we mostly seem to talk about when we talk about "the meanings of sentences." E.g., "Time is now 12:45pm on such and such a date and in such and such a place."
(4) Literal Contextual Propositional Content meaning--which is a direct function of (1), (2), (3) and our attempt to makes sense of something truth-valuable (a proposition) the speaker/writer asserts by his use of contextual sentence-meaning in (3). E.g., Ibid above.
(5) Non-Literal Author/Speaker Intended or Implied meaning (Gricean Implicature, perhaps?)--which is inductively inferred from (1), (2), (3) [and/or (4)], and our own pre-knowledge of what someone most likely would have meant if that person were in context (C). E.g., None exists with respect to the example above. The speaker or writer didn't imply anything that was different from the literal contextual propositional content meaning above.
(6) One's Overall Purpose of Language Use in different conversational contexts (in adverstisements, philosophy class, at a football game).

All are very different things.

This should be obvious: we don't always succeed in meaning what we literally say--either by choice, mistake, or failed intention. Sometimes we mean exactly what we want to mean by literally saying what we mean. Somtimes, by mistake, we use "Bob" instead of "Bill" to refer to Bill. Sometimes we want to imply something else different than what our words literally mean. And sometimes we intend to assert something (a proposition) but don't succeed in expressing any proposition at all by our very own poor choice of words in conveying the contents of our beliefs to an audience.
 
Extrain
 
Reply Sat 17 Apr, 2010 08:17 pm
@kennethamy,
Quote:
Originally Posted by Ahab
Because it is not the name of a real coyote. It is the name of an imaginary coyote.
Isn't the basis for the claim of reference failure that "Wile E. Coyote" is the name of a real coyote but there is no such coyote?


kennethamy;144569 wrote:
No. To say of a proper noun or a noun phrase that it fails to refer is to say of it that it is a referring term, but that what it allegedly refers to does not exist. So there need not be a referent. "Abraham Lincoln" is a referring term that succeeds in referring. But "Wile" is a referring term that fails to refer. "The first man on Mars" is a referring term, but we do not know whether or not it succeeds in referring or not.


Ken, my apologies for breaking this topic open again, but I still find problems with how you are approaching it.

I am not sure why you say this in bold above, but then....

kennethamy;144588 wrote:

First of all, only some terms are referring terms. Those that succeed in referring refer to what exists. What else? But there are no fictional objects. So, referring terms cannot succeed in referring to them. One of your premises is false namdly, there are terms which refer to fictional objects. "Refer" is a success term. Like the term, "win (the race)". It is not a process term like, "run (the race)". Unless there is a finish line, no participant can win a race. And, unless there is an object, no term can succeed in referring".


...say this in bold here. Your view is an explicit contradiction.

Since "refer" is a success term--a transitive verb--then, (contrary to your repeated contention) necessarily "Wiley E. Coyote" is not a referring term. It therefore is not a name, since all names successfully refer.

This same error creeps up everywhere among students. In fact, I had to explicitly articulate in detail the contradiction to Fast earlier in this thread because you had (unknowingly) misled him.
 
kennethamy
 
Reply Sat 17 Apr, 2010 10:09 pm
@Extrain,
Extrain;153359 wrote:
Ken, my apologies for breaking this topic open again, but I still find problems with how you are approaching it.

I am not sure why you say this in bold above, but then....



...say this in bold here. Your view is an explicit contradiction.

Since "refer" is a success term--a transitive verb--then, (contrary to your repeated contention) necessarily "Wiley E. Coyote" is not a referring term. It therefore is not a name, since all names successfully refer.

This same error kreeps up everywhere among students. In fact, I had to explicitly articulate in detail this contradiction to Fast earlier in this thread because you had (unknowingly) misled him.


Yes, I admit that the second sentence in bold needs fixing up. But I did not say that "Wiley E. Coyote"is not a referring term. I said that it fails to refer. And why do all names successfully refer? Isn't "Wiley E. Coyote" a name? What is the error that students keep making?
 
Extrain
 
Reply Sat 17 Apr, 2010 11:43 pm
@kennethamy,
kennethamy;153416 wrote:
Yes, I admit that the second sentence in bold needs fixing up. But I did not say that "Wiley E. Coyote"is not a referring term. I said that it fails to refer. And why do all names successfully refer? Isn't "Wiley E. Coyote" a name? What is the error that students keep making?


The error is to think referring terms can fail to refer. To think this would be a contradiction because then the term both does and does not refer, so the term both is and is not a referring term. Contradiction. On the contrary, referring terms never fail to refer.

"Referring" is not a static predicate, it is dynamic--just as "kicking," "shopping," and "pointing" are dynamic predicates. I am sure this is where the confusion often lies.

Notice, how can I be pointing while failing to point, or be shopping while faling to shop? Or how can a term be referring while failing to refer? So long as I am shopping, I am a shopping person. So long as I am pointing, I am a pointing person. So long as a term is referring, it is a referring term.

So names must always successfully refer, because that is just what names do. That is their sole function. If a word does not refer, then that word is necessarily not a name.

Therefore, since "Wiley E. Coyote" does not refer to anything, it is not a referring term.
 
Owen phil
 
Reply Sun 18 Apr, 2010 03:21 am
@Extrain,
Extrain;153454 wrote:
The error is to think referring terms can fail to refer. To think this would be a contradiction because then the term both does and does not refer, so the term both is and is not a referring term. Contradiction. On the contrary, referring terms never fail to refer.

"Referring" is not a static predicate, it is dynamic--just as "kicking," "shopping," and "pointing" are dynamic predicates. I am sure this is where the confusion often lies.

Notice, how can I be pointing while failing to point, or be shopping while faling to shop? Or how can a term be referring while failing to refer? So long as I am shopping, I am a shopping person. So long as I am pointing, I am a pointing person. So long as a term is referring, it is a referring term.

So names must always successfully refer, because that is just what names do. That is their sole function. If a word does not refer, then that word is necessarily not a name.

Therefore, since "Wiley E. Coyote" does not refer to anything, it is not a referring term.


I don't agree.

Names are words we use to refer.
Names do refer or names do not refer.
Vulcan is the name given to 'that planet which accounts for the unusual orbit of Mercury within the context of Newtonian physics'.
Vulcan does not refer to anything because there is no such planet..by observation. Vulcan is a non-referring name.

The reference of a name or a referring description is the object named or the object described, if such there be.
Vulcan exists, is false.
We cannot grant existence to a thing on the basis that it has a name.
eg. God exists, does not follow simply because "God" is a name.

The name 'Wiley E. Coyote' refers to the fictional character within the context of the cartoon/story.
Wiley E. Coyote is a Coyote, is true within the context of the cartoon/story, but it is false in reality.
Santa wears black boots, is also (confirmed) true only within the context of the Santa story, but it is false within the context of reality.

Pegasus flies, is true within the Pegasus story, and it implies 'Pegasus exists' within the context of the story, even though Pegasus does not refer to anything in reality.
It is not the case that (the present king of France is bald), is true, ..even though the present king of France does not refer or exist in the present world.

If a name or description does not refer then that thing referred to by the name or description does not exist.

The name 'Vulcan' does exist even though it does not refer.
The description 'the present king of France' does exist even though it does not refer at the present time.

(the present king of France) is a referring description that does not refer.
(the whole number between 1 and 2) is a referring description that does not refer, etc. etc.
 
Extrain
 
Reply Sun 18 Apr, 2010 05:08 am
@Owen phil,
Owen;153480 wrote:
I don't agree.

Names are words we use to refer.
Names do refer or names do not refer.
Vulcan is the name given to 'that planet which accounts for the unusual orbit of Mercury within the context of Newtonian physics'.
Vulcan does not refer to anything because there is no such planet..by observation. Vulcan is a non-referring name.


Fair enough. I can agree. Nevertheless, I still contend that no referring term is non-referring, and all non-referring names are empty names. To think otherwise is to assert a contradiction.

"Richard Nixon" still refers to Richard Nixon, even though Nixon is dead. The past and future are no less-real than the present. "Richard Nixon" doesn't suddenly stop referring to Nixon once Nixon dies.

Owen;153480 wrote:
The name 'Wiley E. Coyote' refers to the fictional character within the context of the cartoon/story.
Wiley E. Coyote is a Coyote, is true within the context of the cartoon/story, but it is false in reality.


I disagree. What is true and false is not dependent on linguistic frameworks. Existence, Truth, Reference, and Reality have univocal meanings across all English-like linguistic contexts, not a plurality of meanings, since the following semantic principle I hold to be true:

(T) For a sentence of the form "F(a)", of any language, to be true, the singular term "a" must refer to something existent.

Take, for instance, the token statement:

(S) "Sherlock Holmes is a detective."

There is only one reality, and all things that exist are parts of that reality.

So if (S) is false in the physical world, then (S) is also false within the context of the story. If, however, this is true within the story written by Arthur Conan Doyle, then it is also true in the physical world. Let's suppose, as you say, that "Sherlock Holmes" refers only to a fictional character in the story written by Arthur conan Doyle, but not to any flesh and blood person. Though not referring to any flesh and blood person, then by truth of the semantic principle (T), "Sherlock Holmes" is a singular term purportedly referring to some existent object, however abstract that object is. And if "Sherlock Holmes is a singular referring term, then "Sherlock Holmes" necessarily refers to Sherlock Holmes the abstract object. But if Sherlock Holmes is an abstract object, and not a physical object, then Sherlock Holmes cannot possess ordinary physical properties. So "Sherlock Holmes is a detective" is still false, even if Sherlock Holmes refers to an abstract object.

So (S) is false both inside and outside Arthur Conan Doyle's story because either it is a statement purportedly about a non-existent entity, or a statment about a really existent abstract entity, but for which that abstract entity fails to possess the property of being a detective.

So the most one can salvage with respect to preserving the intuitive truth-value of (S) is to paraphrase it to say,

(S') "Sherlock Holmes is a detective" is found in, or implied by, the story written by Arthur Conan Doyle.

But (S') is not about Sherlock Holmes at all, but only about the story. So, (S') is true, and (S) is false. Therefore, one cannot say anything literally truth-valuable about Sherlock Holmes if Sherlock Holmes doesn't exist.

Quote:
Santa wears black boots, is also (confirmed) true only within the context of the Santa story, but it is false within the context of reality.


This is false. "Santa wear black boots" is true or false irrespective of the linguistic framework within which this statement is found.

Though actual contexts affect the truth-values of propositions, linguistic contexts don't affect truth-values, if the English words mean the same thing across different linguistic frameworks.

Quote:
Pegasus flies, is true within the Pegasus story, and it implies 'Pegasus exists' within the context of the story, even though Pegasus does not refer to anything in reality.


No. Like Quine before me, I contend that "existence" is univocal, and one is committed to the existence of said entities if and only if one is willing to quantify over these entities in order for one's statements about these entities to be true.

Owen;153480 wrote:
It is not the case that (the present king of France is bald), is true, ..even though the present king of France does not refer or exist in the present world.


Right, because "the present King of France" is a Russelian definite description (not a name) and nothing satisfies the quantified statement now in which this assertion is embedded.

Owen;153480 wrote:
(the present king of France) is a referring description that does not refer.
(the whole number between 1 and 2) is a referring description that does not refer, etc. etc.


These are contradictions since definite descriptions that are purportedly referring cannot simultaneously not-refer.

Definite descriptions do not refer, at least not according to Russell. The role of reference-fixing is taken over by Quantifiers. And "the present" acts as indexical description which determines the referent of the description in any given present time.

The past and future are just as really existent as the present. So once a name refers, it always refers. Definite descriptions, on the other hand, can be satisfied by a multitude of objects. Only quantification guarantees that the definite description is satisfied by one and only one object, so long as there are no other entities satsifying the quantified statement.
 
Owen phil
 
Reply Sun 18 Apr, 2010 09:17 am
@Extrain,
Extrain;153506 wrote:
Fair enough. I can agree. Nevertheless, I still contend that no referring term is non-referring, and all non-referring names are empty names. To think otherwise is to assert a contradiction.


Thanks for your interestin reply.

If names refer or not, which you apparently agree with, then empty names do not refer, yet they are still names.
Vulcan is a name (a referring term) and Vulcan does not refer.
The present king of France, is a referring term that does not refer.
What contradiction results from assuming that Vulcan is a referring term?

Extrain;153506 wrote:

"Richard Nixon" still refers to Richard Nixon, even though Nixon is dead. The past and future are no less-real than the present. "Richard Nixon" doesn't suddenly stop referring to Nixon once Nixon dies.


I don't agree here.
"Richard Nixon"stops referring when Richard Nixon is not alive.
~(Richard Nixon is alive) -> Richard Nixon exists...is false.
There is no thing that Richard Nixon is, at the present time.

The name "Richard Nixon" refers to the living person Richard Nixon.
If Richard Nixon is not alive or is not a person, then the name refers to no thing at all.
Nixon's body may have some sense of existence but, Richard Nixon does not.

"The past and future are no less-real than the present."

The past is not part of reality, if we define reality as all that currently is.
The past is part of reality if we define reality as all that currently is and all that previously was.
The future is not a part of reality unless or until the future is present.
Future tense statements are not knowable, imo.

Richard Nixon, relates to the timeframe in which he was alive.
We can only refer to him in the past tense.
There is no property that (Richard Nixon) has.

Extrain;153506 wrote:

I disagree. What is true and false is not dependent on linguistic frameworks. Existence, Truth, Reference, and Reality have univocal meanings across all English-like linguistic contexts, not a plurality of meanings, since the following semantic principle I hold to be true:

(T) For a sentence of the form "F(a)", of any language, to be true, the singular term "a" must refer to something existent.


Yes, Quine: to be something is to be equal to some existent thing.
E!x <-> Ey(x=y).

The names: Santa, Sherlock, Pegasus, Vulcan, etc. are not values of the individual variable at all...because they don't refer.
Perhaps a 'free' logic would be more suitable to deal with non-referring names.

Extrain;153506 wrote:

Take, for instance, the token statement:

(S) "Sherlock Holmes is a detective."

There is only one reality, and all things that exist are parts of that reality.

So if (S) is false in the physical world, then (S) is also false within the context of the story. If, however, this is true within the story written by Arthur Conan Doyle, then it is also true in the physical world. Let's suppose, as you say, that "Sherlock Holmes" refers only to a fictional character in the story written by Arthur conan Doyle, but not to any flesh and blood person. Though not referring to any flesh and blood person, then by truth of the semantic principle (T), "Sherlock Holmes" is a singular term purportedly referring to some existent object, however abstract that object is. And if "Sherlock Holmes is a singular referring term, then "Sherlock Holmes" necessarily refers to Sherlock Holmes the abstract object. But if Sherlock Holmes is an abstract object, and not a physical object, then Sherlock Holmes cannot possess ordinary physical properties. So "Sherlock Holmes is a detective" is still false, even if Sherlock Holmes refers to an abstract object.

So (S) is false both inside and outside Arthur Conan Doyle's story because either it is a statement purportedly about a non-existent entity, or a statment about a really existent abstract entity, but for which that abstract entity fails to possess the property of being a detective.

So the most one can salvage with respect to preserving the intuitive truth-value of (S) is to paraphrase it to say,

(S') "Sherlock Holmes is a detective" is found in, or implied by, the story written by Arthur Conan Doyle.

But (S') is not about Sherlock Holmes at all, but only about the story. So, (S') is true, and (S) is false. Therefore, one cannot say anything literally truth-valuable about Sherlock Holmes if Sherlock Holmes doesn't exist.


But, can't we say 'Sherlock Homes doesn't exist, is true.' ?

The name Sherlock Holmes is a described character that only has meaning with reference to the story.

Sherlock homes is a detective, is true within the context of the story.
Sherlock Homes is a detective, is false in the context of current reality.

The default context is current reality unless otherwise specified.

Truth is that which can be shown to be the case within some context.

A exists, means, there is some property that A has..within some specified context.

(Sherlock is a detective -> Sherlock exists) within the story.

If Sherlock is a detective, is quoted verbatum from the story then it is true within the story.

Extrain;153506 wrote:

This is false. "Santa wear black boots" is true or false irrespective of the linguistic framework within which this statement is found.

Though actual contexts affect the truth-values of propositions, linguistic contexts don't affect truth-values, if the English words mean the same thing across different linguistic frameworks.



No. Like Quine before me, I contend that "existence" is univocal, and one is committed to the existence of said entities if and only if one is willing to quantify over these entities in order for one's statements about these entities to be true.



Right, because "the present King of France" is a Russelian definite description (not a name) and nothing satisfies the quantified statement now in which this assertion is embedded.



These are contradictions since definite descriptions that are purportedly referring cannot simultaneously not-refer.


Extrain;153506 wrote:

Definite descriptions do not refer, at least not according to Russell. The role of reference-fixing is taken over by Quantifiers. And "the present" acts as indexical description which determines the referent of the description in any given present time.

The past and future are just as really existent as the present. So once a name refers, it always refers. Definite descriptions, on the other hand, can be satisfied by a multitude of objects. Only quantification guarantees that the definite description is satisfied by one and only one object, so long as there are no other entities satsifying the quantified statement.


Russell proves: (the xMad=a) = a, ie. the description (the xMad=a) refers in exactly the same way that a refers.

If a description exists E!(the x:Fx) then it is a value of the individual variable.

E!(the x:Fx) <-> EyAx(x=y <-> Fx).
E!(the x:Fx) <-> Ey((the x:Fx)=y).
E!(the x:Fx) <-> (the x:Fx)=(the x:Fx)
E!(the x:Fx) <-> F(the x:Fx).
E!(the x:Fx) <-> EG(G(the x:Fx)).
etc.

Russell also claims that E!a has no meaning in philosophy, but...
E!(the xMad=a) <-> EyAx(x=y <-> x=a)
E!(the xMad=a) <-> Ey(y=a)
E!(the xMad=a) <-> a exists.

(the xMad=a)=a -> (E!(the xMad=a) <-> E!a), by Leibniz's Law.
 
Extrain
 
Reply Sun 18 Apr, 2010 03:28 pm
@Owen phil,
[QUOTE=Owen;153576] If names refer or not, which you apparently agree with, then empty names do not refer, yet they are still names.[/QUOTE]
Owen;153576 wrote:

Vulcan is a name (a referring term) and Vulcan does not refer.
The present king of France, is a referring term that does not refer.


"The Present King of France" is not a referring term because it is not a name, and Logic dictates a name can refer to one and only one thing at a time. If "The Present King of France" were a referring term, then "The Present King" would refer to every King of France. But it does not. Therefore, "The Present King of France" is not a referring term. See below.

[QUOTE=Owen;153576] What contradiction results from assuming that Vulcan is a referring term?[/QUOTE]

Once a name refers, it always refers. If a name does not refer, it never refers. When we took ourselves to be talking about Vulcan, we were never talking about anything. Hence, "Vulcan" was never a referring term. If "Vulcan" is a referring term that fails to refer, then "Vulcan" both is and is not a referring term because "Vulcan" would then both refer and not refer--contradiction.

[QUOTE=Owen;153576] I don't agree here.[/QUOTE]
Owen;153576 wrote:

"Richard Nixon"stops referring when Richard Nixon is not alive.
~(Richard Nixon is alive) -> Richard Nixon exists...is false.
There is no thing that Richard Nixon is, at the present time.


~(Richard Nixon is alive now) --> Richard exists now...is indeed false, and Richard Nixon exists now is indeed false. But that "Richard Nixon" refers now to Richard Nixon is indeed true in all times and places past, present, and future.

If "Richard Nixon" does not now refer to Richard Nixon in the past, as it seems you want to imply, then,

Richard Nixon was once the President of the United States

would be false. But this statement is true. So "Richard Nixon" still refers to Richard Nixon now.

[QUOTE=Owen;153576] The name "Richard Nixon" refers to the living person Richard Nixon.[/QUOTE]

True.

[QUOTE=Owen;153576] If Richard Nixon is not alive or is not a person, then the name refers to no thing at all.[/QUOTE]

This is false. Richard Nixon does not have to be alive now for "Richard Nixon" to still refer to Nixon who existed in the past. That Richard Nixon was behind the WaterGate Scandal...is still true. Therefore, "Richard Nixon" refers now to Richard Nixon, even though Richard Nixon is now dead. What reason do you have for thinking the property of being-present is a necessary condition for something to exist? Surely, Richard Nixon exists in the past, does he not? Why can we not refer to things existing in the past? Because the past doesn't exist? If the past doesn't exist, then all historical propositions we thought were true (and are true now) are actually false. But this is absurd.

[QUOTE]Nixon's body may have some sense of existence but, Richard Nixon does not.[/QUOTE]



[QUOTE=Owen;153576]The past is not part of reality, if we define reality as all that currently is.[/QUOTE]

I do not define reality as "all that currently is." I define reality as "all that ever is, was, and has been."

You apparently think only the present time exists, and that the past and future don't exist. But this is clearly false, since, suppose the metaphysical thesis of Presentism were true: then "George W. Bush was President of the United States" is false. But this is true. Therefore, past times exist no less than the present times (or future times). Existence does not come in "degrees."

[QUOTE=Owen;153576] The past is part of reality if we define reality as all that currently is and all that previously was.[/QUOTE]

True.

[QUOTE=Owen;153576] The future is not a part of reality unless or until the future is present.[/QUOTE]

I think this is false. What exists in the future may not be present. But being-present is not a necessary condition for something to exist. Things don't exist "necessarily in the present." For, if they did, then all things would exist at once-which is clearly false. Richard Nixon only exists in the past. Richard Nixon does not exist in the present.

[QUOTE=Owen;153576] Future tense statements are not knowable, imo.[/QUOTE]

Even if this were true (which it is not), just because future statements are unknowable doesn't entail future events don't exist.

[QUOTE] Richard Nixon, relates to the timeframe in which he was alive.[/QUOTE]

I might agree if I knew what you meant by "Nixon relating to a time-frame." I am not sure what you mean by "relating to a time-frame." Physical objects exist only within time, but surely I can still presently refer to Nixon who exists in the past but not in the present.

[QUOTE=Owen;153576]We can only refer to him in the past tense.[/QUOTE]

This is false. "Richard Nixon" still refers to Nixon now, even if Richard Nixon exists only in the past. However, it is true that we can only ascribe properties to Nixon in the past tense, such as in the statement "Nixon was the President of the United States."

[QUOTE=Owen;153576]There is no property that (Richard Nixon) has.[/QUOTE]

True. But there are properties that Richard Nixon had.

[QUOTE=Owen;153576]Yes, Quine: to be something is to be equal to some existent thing.[/QUOTE]
Owen;153576 wrote:

E!x <-> Ey(x=y).

The names: Santa, Sherlock, Pegasus, Vulcan, etc. are not values of the individual variable at all...because they don't refer.
Perhaps a 'free' logic would be more suitable to deal with non-referring names.

Yes.

[QUOTE=Owen;153576] But, can't we say 'Sherlock Homes doesn't exist, is true.' ?[/QUOTE]

Colloquially, in natural language, yes, we can. But strictly speaking, in logic, we cannot, unless (like Russell) "Sherlock Holmes" is not a name but a disguised definite description, such that,

~(Ex) Sx is true.

[QUOTE=Owen;153576] The name Sherlock Holmes is a described character that only has meaning with reference to the story.[/QUOTE]

It is true that "Sherlock Holmes" has meaning only with reference to a story. And it might be true that Sherlock Holmes is a character in a story. But it is false that Sherlock Holmes is a detective in a story, and that Sherlock Holmes has arms and legs in a story. Real flesh and blood persons don't have arms and legs in stories. Nor do fictional characters have arms or legs, if fictional characters exist. So it is literally false that Sherlock Holmes has arms and legs, assuming Sherlock Holmes is an existent abstract object in a story, since abstract (non-physical) objects cannot have arms and legs.

[QUOTE=Owen;153576] Sherlock homes is a detective, is true within the context of the story. Sherlock Homes is a detective, is false in the context of current reality.[/QUOTE]

No, this is not correct. Take the statement again.

"Sherlock Holmes is a detective."

If the words in this statement have the same meaning both inside and outside a story (which they clearly do), then "Sherlock Holmes is a detective" is literally false both inside and outside the story. Linguistic contexts don't change word-meanings. Like I said, the statement is false either because,

(1) "Sherlock Holmes" does not refer to Sherlock Holmes, or,
(2) "Sherlock Holmes" refers to Sherlock Holmes, but Sherlock Holmes is an abstract object, and abstract objects are not detectives, since being-a-detective is a property only physical objects can possess, and Sherlock Holmes is not a physical object.

Owen;153576The default context is current reality unless otherwise specified. [COLOR=black wrote:
Truth is that which can be shown to be the case within some context.[/COLOR]


Again, real-world context will affect truth-values of indexicals such as "You are 25 years old," since "You" refers to different people within different contexts. But there are no such as things as different linguistic contexts. If there were, then the words in each English context would have different meanings. But they don't. So there doesn't exist more than one English context.

[QUOTE=Owen;153576] A exists, means, there is some property that A has..within some specified context.[/QUOTE]

This is false. Existence is not a property, nor is it a predicate. Nor is it an indexical property or predicate like present, past, future.

[QUOTE=Owen;153576] (Sherlock is a detective -> Sherlock exists) within the story.[/QUOTE]
Owen;153576 wrote:


If Sherlock is a detective, is quoted verbatum from the story then it is true within the story.


If this is true, then there are alternate meanings of exist, such as exist*, alternate meanings of true, such as true*, and alternate meanings of refer, such as refer*. But this is false, "exist," "true," and "refer" have one and only one literal meaning. They don't have figurative meanings.

[QUOTE=Owen;153576] Russell proves: (the xMad=a) = a, ie. the description (the xMad=a) refers in exactly the same way that a refers.[/QUOTE]
Owen;153576 wrote:


E!(the x:Fx) <-> EyAx(x=y <-> Fx).
E!(the x:Fx) <-> Ey((the x:Fx)=y).
E!(the x:Fx) <-> (the x:Fx)=(the x:Fx)
E!(the x:Fx) <-> F(the x:Fx).
E!(the x:Fx) <-> EG(G(the x:Fx)).
etc.

Russell also claims that E!a has no meaning in philosophy, but...
E!(the xMad=a) <-> EyAx(x=y <-> x=a)
E!(the xMad=a) <-> Ey(y=a)
E!(the xMad=a) <-> a exists.

(the xMad=a)=a -> (E!(the xMad=a) <-> E!a), by Leibniz's Law.



[QUOTE=Owen;153576] If a description exists E!(the x:Fx) then it is a value of the individual variable.[/QUOTE]

Russell was wrong. Descriptions are simply not values of individual variables, in spite of the fact that Russell had thought he proved descriptions refer the same way that names refer. On the contrary, descriptions are functions which map individuals (arguments) to values.

For instance, Berlin is the value of the function expressed by "the Capital of x" when its argument is Germany, just as Louis the 9th is the value of the function "the present King of France" when the description is uttered hundreds of years ago. So descriptions do NOT have referential capacity across different times.

Similarly, "the present King of France is bald" is a complex function which maps individuals and properties to truth values. The description "The present King of France" is unsaturated now since nothing satisfies it, so the quantified statement within which this description is embedded is false now (or truth-valueless-depending on your own ontology concerning structured propositions).
 
Ahab
 
Reply Sun 18 Apr, 2010 06:17 pm
@Extrain,
Extrain;153506 wrote:
I disagree. What is true and false is not dependent on linguistic frameworks. Existence, Truth, Reference, and Reality have univocal meanings across all English-like linguistic contexts, not a plurality of meanings, since the following semantic principle I hold to be true:

(T) For a sentence of the form "F(a)", of any language, to be true, the singular term "a" must refer to something existent.

Take, for instance, the token statement:

(S) "Sherlock Holmes is a detective."



I don't happen to share your concept of reference. Reference does not presuppose reality or existence. It presupposes identifiability.

So it must be possible to specify what we are talking about, either through a name or description or by ostension. Whatever we can identify, we can refer to and quantify over. And that, of couse, includes fictional characters.

So it is true that Sherlock Holmes was a detective and that he lived at 221b Baker Street. And it is aso true that Sherlock Holmes is not a real person. Fictional characters are representations of imaginary persons.

Pace Quine, not everything exists, nor is everything real.Smile
 
Extrain
 
Reply Sun 18 Apr, 2010 07:29 pm
@Ahab,
Ahab;153771 wrote:
I don't happen to share your concept of reference. Reference does not presuppose reality or existence. It presupposes identifiability.


Then you would be wrong. It is contrary to the obviously true semantic principle,

(T) For a sentence of the form "F(a)", of any language, to be true, the singular term "a" must refer to something existent.

"To refer" is a success term. So to be a referring term, necessarily something must exist to which the term is referring. If a term does not refer, then necessarily, that term is not a referring term. To think otherwise, is to involve oneself in a contradiction.(I am pretty sure we already went over this once before.)

Ahab;153771 wrote:
So it must be possible to specify what we are talking about, either through a name or description or by ostension. Whatever we can identify, we can refer to and quantify over.


I've replied to this same remark before in my discussion with Fast on this thread: The context in which the name-type "John" is used, for instance, must be identified before one knows whether the speaker is using the token-name "John1" or token-name "John2." But once we know the context, necessarily, "John" refers to John and no one else named by that same name-type.

Unfortunately, you're being sloppy here. Don't confuse the notion of satisfaction with the notion of reference. And don't confuse the notion of reference with the notion of denotation.

Descriptions don't refer. Ostension refers. Names refer.

The description "the present King of France" could be satisfied by any of the French Kings in history when this very same description is uttered at different times in history. So, "the present King of France" is not a referring term. Only names are referring terms.

Quantifiers such as "All" "some" and "something" are not referring terms, but merely place-holders that specify the domain over which they quantify. "(Ex) Fx" is true if and only if at least one object is a F. "(Ax) Fx" is true if and only if all objects are F's.

Ahab;153771 wrote:
And that, of couse, includes fictional characters.
So it is true that Sherlock Holmes was a detective and that he lived at 221b Baker Street. And it is aso true that Sherlock Holmes is not a real person. Fictional characters are representations of imaginary persons.


No, this isn't correct at all. Just think about what you're saying.

I have no problem about someone countenancing the literal existence of fictional characters such as Sherlock Holmes as abstract objects. But these abstract object don't have any properties of their own, and hence, it is quite futile to postulate their literal existence since abstract objects don't have arms or legs, nor can abstract objects speak are solve mysteries, nor can they live on Baker Street. So there is no reason to be supposing they exist anyway. They don't do any explanatory work; they don't make statement such as "Sherlock Holmes is a detective" true: not at all. "Sherlock Holmes is a detective" is literally false, even if Sherlock Holmes is an existent abstract object.

This is a good instance of a violation of Ockham's Razor that says "don't multiply entities needlessly."


Ahab;153771 wrote:
Pace Quine, not everything exists, nor is everything real.Smile


"Pace Quine"? Everything you just said would be considered anti-Quinean.

"Identifiability" is an epistemic notion, not an ontological notion. And though Quine might share that notion with you, it is not a necessary condition for saying or believing that something exists.

Quine's Criterion of Ontological commitment does not tell us what exists, or how we know that something exists, but what we are committed to when we say that something exists. If you think Sherlock Holmes exists, then necessarily (a la Quine), you are committed to the literal existence of Sherlock Holmes--either as an abstract entity, or as real person--and both notions are clearly false.
 
Ahab
 
Reply Sun 18 Apr, 2010 07:50 pm
@Extrain,
Extrain;153793 wrote:
Then you would be wrong. "To refer" is a success term. So to be a referring term, necessarily something must exist to which the term is referring. If a term does not refer, then necessarily, that term is not a referring term. To think otherwise, is to involve yourself in a contradiction.(I am pretty sure we already went over this once before.)


If we can identify what we are referring to then we can successfully refer to it. And that includes fictional characters.
You seem to be missing the point that we are dealing with different conceptions of reference.
You presuppose existence. I presuppose identifiability.

Quote:
I've replied to this same remark before in my discussion with Fast on this thread: The context in which the name-type "John," for instance, has to be identified before one knows whether the speaker is using the token-name "John1" or token-name "John2." But given the context, necessarily. "John" refers to John and no one else named by that same name-type.

Unfortunately, you're being sloppy here. Don't confuse the notion of satisfaction with the notion of reference. And don't confuse the notion of reference with the notion of denotation.

Descriptions don't refer. Ostension refers. Names refer.

The description "the present King of France" could be satisfied by any of the French Kings in history when this very same description is uttered at different times in history. So, "the present King of France" is not a referring term. Only names are referring terms.


No. I'm not being sloppy. I never claimed that every description would enable us to identify what is being referred to. I could say I saw the present Queen of England on the tube and others would know to whom I was referring because that description does enable others to identify the referent: Queen Elizabeth II.

Quote:
"Pace Quine"? Everything you just said would be considered anti-Quinean.


Of course. I don't agree with Quine on this question. 'Pace' is used to politely express that disagreement.
 
Extrain
 
Reply Sun 18 Apr, 2010 08:08 pm
@Ahab,
Ahab;153803 wrote:
If we can identify what we are referring to then we can successfully refer to it.


That's trivially true because it is a tautology. "If P, then P." If I can identify what I am referring to, then of course I can successfully refer to it.

Ahab;153803 wrote:
And that includes fictional characters.


But this is false. Fictional characters don't exist. So we haven't identified any existent characters. You may have identified a certain range of descriptions in the story associated with the purported name "Sherlock Holmes," but you haven't identified Sherlock Holmes. This is false. See next.

(I happen to be a theist, and I am not sure where you stand. But let me ask you this: have you identified God just because "God" as a name is mentioned in the Bible?" I seriously doubt any atheist would agree with you that just because you use a name that purportedly refers, that you have thereby identified that entity as existent.)

Ahab;153803 wrote:
You presuppose existence. I presuppose identifiability.


huh? Identifiability is certainly a necessary condition to refer to something, but it is not a sufficient condition to refer to something. Something must also exist to which I am referring in order to refer at all.
Again, we cannot refer to non-existent things.

Ahab;153803 wrote:
You seem to be missing the point that we are dealing with different conceptions of reference.


And I have already said that "reference" has one and only one meaning. To suppose otherwise is to introduce different kinds of existence into the world--for which I think there is only one. I truly don't understand what it means when someone says "the chair exists differently than my thoughts." A la Kant, "existence" is not a predicate. "Existence" is a place-holder for all objects that exist. There are not different "ways" of existing. (I may have to refer you to my other post on this matter in Kennethamy's thread titled "Ways of Existing.")

Ahab;153803 wrote:
No. I'm not being sloppy. I never claimed that every description would enable us to identify what is being referred to. I could say I saw the present Queen of England on the tube and others would know to whom I was referring because that description does enable others to identify the referent: Queen Elizabeth II.


Ok, but you certainly implied that's what you were saying.

In any case, I agree. Descriptions help us identify the thing we are talking about. But still, descriptions don't refer in and of themselves. You need context, in this case "who it was you saw on the television".
 
 

 
Copyright © 2025 MadLab, LLC :: Terms of Service :: Privacy Policy :: Page generated in 0.03 seconds on 01/11/2025 at 05:53:54