Get Email Updates • Email this Topic • Print this Page
In The Problems of Philosophy, Russell discusses the principle of induction: roughly, if A and B have been found associated a great number of times, and never dissociated, the it is probable A will be associated with B in a fresh instance.
I believe, for example, the sun will probably rise tomorrow, since it has risen every other day. But I can't say in what the truth of this belief subsists. Tomorrow will come, and the sun will either rise or not rise - in won't probably rise.
Russell also says that experience can neither prove nor disprove one's belief in the principle of induction. But I don't understand his reasons, and his argument loses me at that point. This is completely because, as I stated, I don't see what the truth of the principle has to do with experience at all. What could one possibly experience to validate the belief that a A will probably be associated with B? As before, either A will or will not be associated with B in experience.
I must still be confused. Or perhaps he has a bad way of making his point. Russell seems to say that principle of induction cannot be proven by experience. (Roughly, if A and B have been found associated a great number of times, and never dissociated, then it is probable A will be associated with B in a fresh instance.) My reaction is that of course it can't be proven, for what could prove the belief that the sun will probably rise tomorrow?
But if he just wants to make the case that there can be no certain knowledge of things with which we aren't acquainted, or that it is misplaced to "fault inductive justification for not producing certainty," why does he constantly emphasize the word "probably?"
"induction" means that reality is essentially mythical;
In ordinary terms:
Que Sera, Sera,
Whatever will be, will be
The future's not ours, to see
Que Sera, Sera
What will be, will be.
:eek:
Some bad news for narrow minded bullet dodgers:
The future extends from now to infinity.
You are going to be a long time dead.
In The Problems of Philosophy, Russell discusses the principle of induction: roughly, if A and B have been found associated a great number of times, and never dissociated, the it is probable A will be associated with B in a fresh instance.
I believe, for example, the sun will probably rise tomorrow, since it has risen every other day. But I can't say in what the truth of this belief subsists. Tomorrow will come, and the sun will either rise or not rise - in won't probably rise.
Russell also says that experience can neither prove nor disprove one's belief in the principle of induction. But I don't understand his reasons, and his argument loses me at that point. This is completely because, as I stated, I don't see what the truth of the principle has to do with experience at all. What could one possibly experience to validate the belief that a A will probably be associated with B? As before, either A will or will not be associated with B in experience.
In The Problems of Philosophy, Russell discusses the principle of induction: roughly, if A and B have been found associated a great number of times, and never dissociated, the it is probable A will be associated with B in a fresh instance.
I believe, for example, the sun will probably rise tomorrow, since it has risen every other day. But I can't say in what the truth of this belief subsists. Tomorrow will come, and the sun will either rise or not rise - in won't probably rise.
Russell also says that experience can neither prove nor disprove one's belief in the principle of induction. But I don't understand his reasons, and his argument loses me at that point. This is completely because, as I stated, I don't see what the truth of the principle has to do with experience at all. What could one possibly experience to validate the belief that a A will probably be associated with B? As before, either A will or will not be associated with B in experience.
The statement that the Sun will probably rise tomorrow can be proven in the same way that we can prove that the last marble in an urn will turn out to be red, because all the other marbles we have already drawn from the urn have been red. The more red marbles we draw from the urn, the more probable it is that the next marble we draw will also be red. The we expect the unobserved to resemble the observed. The question of the justification of induction is whether that expectation is justified, and to what extent it is.
For an urn filled halfway with white marbles, then filled the rest of the way with red marbles, our intuition gives an answer directly opposed to reality. In this more specific scenario the more red marbles we've seen so far, the less likely it is that we will get a red one on the next pull.
How did you reach this conclusion?
Thanks, kennethamy. I understand the case you are making. But I would never get it out of Russell's writing. Or maybe his claim is subtler than I understand it to be.
We don't know in the scenario I offered in the first post, and that's the point. I'll try a different format.
The observer in either your scenario or the one I offer has the same information.
Specifically that:
#1:the urn contains marbles
#2:so far, when one was retrieved it was red. (that is we have taken a some number of red marbles from the urn.)
You proposed that this evidence supports the following proposition:
"The next marble will probably be red"
What I was trying to say, is that this proposition is not actually supported by the observed evidence.
Primarily; since we don't know the true contents of the Urn at the beginning, we cannot construct a probability that bears a relationship to the truth. Even though we (that is most people) would tend to come to the same conclusion that you did.
The conclusion simply does not follow from the evidence.
The fact that it would "appear reasonable" to us to assume that it does, is an illustration of the problems we encounter trying to utilize intuition in a way that is rational (I mean rational in the sense that our conclusion bears a relationship to the reality, which in this example it does not.)
Again our expectation is:
"We are more likely to get a red marble next time we draw"
our reason for believing this is:
"Every marble has been red so far"
The problem is illustrated by the fact that we conceive of a class of scenarios where the above would be untrue. One example being that marbles of some color other than red are present in the urn. Now if we had some other evidence we could increase our certainty perhaps. For example If the urn is in a village where there is a strong cultural habit of storing only one color of marble in one urn.
Still this is only ever able to get you to a certain point. That is the kind of intuition that Russel is referring to cannot ever give you a prediction of how a specific event will occur "in fact". The closest you can come is to a high probability. The problem is worse than he seems to be saying however, because out intuition in these cases can lead us to blatantly untrue beliefs if we ignore what we don't know. Importantly, in practice, we usually do ignore the missing information!
Which means that if we are seeking to approach the truth, we must be cautious of our intuition (and statistical and probabilistic methods as well.) They will, by their nature, often lead us in the wrong direction.
I hope this is clearer;
--Quatl
PS, I don't want to give the impression that intuition is useless, as I don't believe that. If the question was to criticize deductive reasoning, I could give you various issues that we encounter with those methods as well. There are many tools in our heads, and the trick is using them all effectively.
Since we have no knowledge of the contents of the jar, why should we think that taking a red marble from the jar does not increase the chances that the next marble will be red? If it doesn't, then there is just as great a chance that we will next draw a blackbird.
PS, I don't want to give the impression that intuition is useless, as I don't believe that. If the question was to criticize deductive reasoning, I could give you various issues that we encounter with those methods as well. There are many tools in our heads, and the trick is using them all effectively.