Get Email Updates • Email this Topic • Print this Page
Right. "Cogent" and "uncogent" do not apply to deductive arguments.
But this isn't a problem for Logic. This is a problem for epistemology and philosophers.
For an argument to be cogent or uncogent, the premises don't have to be known to be true by persons X and Y. Truth and knowledge are not the same.
---------- Post added 04-08-2010 at 01:59 PM ----------
I don't think that's right, Ken. One person may know a premise to be true of a cogent argument, the other person may not.
So knowing that P is not a necessary condition for an argument to be cogent or uncogent. Further, cogent never implies sound, and sound never implies cogent.
But that is how, "cogent" is defined. An argument whose premises are known to be true. If your objection were a good one, then it would apply to the term, "validity" since one person might know that an argument was valid, and another not know that. But, so what?
A proposition which is known need not be known to be known, in order to be known. A person may know that p, and not know he knows that p.
I don't therefore-see that cogent implies sound.
I don't therefore-see that cogent implies sound.
If an argument is valid, then an argument is a deductive argument, and if the premises of a valid (and thus deductive) argument are true, then the argument is a sound (and thus valid and thus deductive) argument, and if the premises are not only true, but known to be true as well (which is what I thought a cogent argument was), then the argument is a cogent argument. But, that an argument is a cogent argument is no good reason to think that an argument is a sound argument (unless I'm mistaken about what a cogent argument is), as the premises of both some unsound deductive arguments and some inductive arguments are known to be true.
It's starting to sound like a cogent argument is more than merely an argument with premises that are known to be true.
huh? Ken, I'm pretty sure you're mistaken. The dictionary may define "cogent" that way. But no logic textbook does. And if it did, it would be wrong. Why would you think this anyway?
Example:
(1) All Presidents of the United States so far have been men.
(2) Therefore, the next president of the United States will probably be a man.
The argument is inductively strong and cogent.
But an alien from outer space does not have to know (1) is true for the argument to be cogent. So the argument's cogency is not dependent on whether this or that individual knows that it is, or whether or not an individual knows that (1) is true. Though a person may not be able to determine whether or not the argument is cogent for him or her self, the argument is cogent regardless of whether this or that individual knows that it is.
Further, what do strong and cogent inductive arguments have to do with valid and sound deductive arguments?
True.
---------- Post added 04-08-2010 at 02:45 PM ----------
[/COLOR]
Because it doesn't. Cogent implies that the argument is strong.
Correct.
This is false. That is not what a cogent argument is.
That's correct--because cogent arguments are not "sound" arguments anyway--cogent arguments are only strong arguments.
Unfortunately, you are mistaken--just as Ken is mistaken.
It's actually less. You guys are making logic say more than it does.
"Cogent" is a technical term. Some logic books discuss it. Some do not even mention it. Copi does not even mention it. I don't see how it is possible I am mistaken about it. I suppose you are using it differently from me. I use it to mean, "the premises are known to be true". You can disagree. But that does not mean I am mistaken. "Cogent" does not have the standard use that "valid" or that "sound" has.
That's right. "cogent" IS a technical term. But then you insist on using "cogent" colloquially all you want. But that doesn't mean you are correct. In fact, your view entails a contradiction:
(1) All presidents of the united states so far have been men.
(2) So, the next president of the united states will probably be a man.
(3) (1)-(2) is a cogent argument.
(4) All cogent arguments are arguments whose premises are known to be true.
(5) ET from outer space does not know that (1) is true.
(6) Therefore, (1)-(2) is not a cogent argument.
(7) Contradiction. [(3) and (6)]
When I say, "known to be true" I mean, a matter of general knowledge or personal knowledge. Something does not have to be known by ET in order to be a matter of general knowledge. That the Moon smaller than Earth is a matter of general knowledge, but some people don't know it, and certainly, ET doesn't know it.
It's actually less. You guys are making logic say more than it does. A "cogent argument' only means that argument is both inductively strong and the premises are true--nothing more, nothing less. A "cogent argument" doesn't mean "the premises have to be known to be true." This is false.
A cogent argument is an argument with premises that are known to be true. We're not saying that a cogent argument is an argument with premises that must be known.
So whose knowledge is necessary for an argument to be cogent? Bob's, Bill's, or ET's? All of them at once? Only some of them? Bob's and Bill's, but not ET's? Your view entails a contradiction if you don't specify this.
Consider the proposition, "Earth is the third planet from the sun." That proposition is true, but more importantly, it's known to be true, as it's common knowledge, but that it's common knowledge doesn't mean that Bob, Bill, nor ET must know that it is true, or even believe that it's common knowledge for that matter.
All that's important is that it is common knowledge. Hence, that it's actually common knowledge, not that it must (must, I say) be common knowledge.
Sure. But none of that is a necessary condition for the argument itself to be cogent or uncogent.
If knowledge was a necessary condition for an argument to be cogent or uncogent, then you would have to specify whose knowledge provides the necessary condition for all cogent arguments to be cogent arguments.
You can't just arbitrarily decide to include person X, Y, and Z's knowledge as necessary conditions, and then exclude ET's knowledge as being a necessary condition.
What do people's knowledge about this or that have anything to do with whether or not arguments are cogent or uncogent?
Why can't the necessary condition just be that it is a matter of general knowledge that the Moon is smaller than Earth. Why could that not be a premise? I don't see that.
That's what the cogency of an argument is. I don't understand your question. This is just a verbal dispute about what "cogent argument" means. It is trivial. I just stipulate that "cogent argument" means that the premises of the argument are known to be true.
But what is supposed to be wrong with such a theory? Why think that whether an argument is deductive or non-deductive is intrinsic to the argument itself? We cam infer intentions from the argument most of the time. And, in the case of a deductive argument, if the argument is valid, then don't we infer the intention of the arguer from the argument (with the help of charity)? After all, we reconstruct arguments by trying to divine the intentions of the arguer too. So, why should we not let the intentions of the arguer be what decides what kind of argument it is?
An intention theory has some odd implications that I don't know if you want to accept. For instance, that there exists valid inductive arguments.
I thought you denied the existence of valid inductive arguments. That would be inconsistent. Otherwise I agree that the theory has some plausibility.
for instance that all deductive arguments are valid.
I also did some more careful analysis introducing a distinction between arguments as a collection of propositions standing in a relation, and one as a collection of sentences.
One idea is to restrict deductive/inductive to sentence-arguments since there are many of them.
Proposition-arguments are not deductive or inductive. At least that was one possibility that I considered.
An intention theory has some odd implications that I don't know if you want to accept. For instance, that there exists valid inductive arguments. We discussed this before. I thought you denied the existence of valid inductive arguments. That would be inconsistent. Otherwise I agree that the theory has some plausibility.
When you say that (what I bolded above, that is), I get the feeling that you think that he thinks there are valid inductive arguments. He doesn't think that, and neither do I, and neither does Extrain. Only you and those that confuse "not valid" with "invalid" think that.
"Invalid" implies "not valid" just as "false" implies "not true," but just as "not true" doesn't imply "false," neither does "not valid" imply "invalid."
All inductive arguments are not valid; hence, no inductive argument is valid, but we are not saying (not at all) that all inductive arguments are invalid, for we do not hold that, as we hold that inductive arguments are neither valid nor invalid--only that they're not valid.
You believe (and I agree) that some propositions are true, and you believe (and I agree) that some propositions are false, and we both believe that if a proposition is false, then we also believe that a proposition is not true, for we both believe (and agree) that "false" implies "not true."
Of course, what we believe, and whether we agree is neither here nor there, as only what matters is if it's all true, but I have taken it upon myself to mention what we believe and whether we agree just so we know exactly where each of us stands.
At this point, not only do we believe and agree that "false" implies "not true," but it's also true that "false" implies "not true," and that is, of course, the important point. However, I (and apparently unlike you) do not believe that the converse is true. What I mean by that is that although the former implies the latter, the latter does not imply the former; hence, I do not believe that "not true" implies "false," but based on your quote, you seem to believe just that, that "not true" does imply false, but you shouldn't believe that, nor should I agree with that, for it's not true.
Now, I suspect that you don't want to take my word for it, and if you didn't take my word for it, I can't say that I would rightly blame you, for I (as you know) have never formally studied any of this and thus do not have the credentials to bring to bare on this, so all I'm left with is the hope that I may be able to muster up an argument to show you that what I say is true, but I am awful at constructing arguments, so I'm left with nothing but what I have that I believe to be good reasons for you to think what I think.
To do that, I turn your attention to a topic you alluded to earlier (in this thread) with Kennethamy. You started talking about sentences and whether they can be (or cannot be) true or false. Incidentally, I do think that some sentences are true and that some sentences are false, but more on that later, if you like.
What I find important is that you think that no sentence is true or false--only that propositions are true or false. But, if it's so that you think no sentence is true, then isn't it also true that you think sentences are not true? And if so, then although you do think sentences are not true, it's still the case that you think no sentence is false, yet you said above, "not true" implies false, but how can that be?
Consider a sentence that fails to express a proposition. Do you have one in mind? You think that the sentence is not true, just as I think the sentence is not true. Additionally, you think that the sentence is not false, just as I think the sentence is not false. Remember, you think that only propositions are true or false. You do not think that sentences are true or false. Yet, isn't it so that we both believe (and agree) that it is not only not true but not false as well?
"Not true" is stronger than "false," so although the former implies the latter, the latter doesn't imply the former.
1. For all propositions, if it is true, then it is not false.
2. For all propositions, if it is false, then it is not true.
3. For all propositions, if it is not true, then it is false.
4. For all propositions, if it is not false, then it is true.
I tentatively believe in all of them (due to certain semantic paradoxes especially the liar paradox). You do not believe all of them, but you believe in 1-2.
I know. I don't know what theory you accept about truth carriers but it does involve sentences. Do you believe that propositions exist too?
I like to use this one:
[INDENT]Chomsky. Colorless green ideas sleep furiously.
[/INDENT]We agree about Chomsky not expressing any proposition, and that the sentence is neither true or false.
About sentences, yes. Analogous to 1-4 above, there is a set for sentences too:
[INDENT]1. For all sentences, if it is true, then it is not false.
2. For all sentences, if it is false, then it is not true.
3. For all sentences, if it is not true, then it is false.
4. For all sentences, if it is not false, then it is true.
[/INDENT]Which ones do you believe in? I believe in 1-2 and disbelieve in 3-4. I think you do likewise. Is that correct?
There is also the sentence version of bivalence:
[INDENT]Sentence bivalence. For all sentences, it is true or false and not true and false.
[/INDENT]I think sentence bivalence is false and not true. I suppose you do the same. Is that so?